part III
|
CHAPTER VII |
SECTION 1.
THE LABOUR-PROCESS
OR THE PRODUCTION OF
USE-VALUES
Labour is, in the first place, a process in which both man and Nature
participate, and in which man of his own accord starts, regulates, and controls
the material re-actions between himself and Nature. He opposes himself to Nature
as one of her own forces, setting in motion arms and legs, head and hands, the
natural forces of his body, in order to appropriate Nature's productions in a
form adapted to his own wants. By thus acting on the external world and changing
it, he at the same time changes his own nature. He develops his slumbering
powers and compels them to act in obedience to his sway. We are not now dealing
with those primitive instinctive forms of labour that remind us of the mere
animal. An immeasurable interval of time separates the state of things in which
The elementary factors of the labour-process are 1, the personal activity of
man, i.e., work itself, 2, the subject of that work, and 3, its
instruments.
The soil (and this, economically speaking, includes water) in the virgin
state in which it supplies [1]
man with necessaries or the means of subsistence ready to hand, exists
independently of him, and is the universal subject of human labour. All those
things which labour merely separates from immediate connexion with their
environment, are subjects of labour spontaneously provided by Nature. Such are
fish which we catch and take from their element, water, timber which we fell in
the virgin forest, and ores which we extract from their veins. If, on the other
hand, the subject of labour has, so to say, been filtered through previous
labour, we call it raw material; such is ore already extracted and ready for
washing. All raw material is the subject of labour, but not every subject of
labour is raw material: it can only become so, after it has undergone some
alteration by means of labour.
An instrument of labour is a thing, or a complex of things, which the
labourer interposes between himself and the subject of his labour, and which
serves as the conductor of his activity. He makes use of the In a wider sense we may include among the instruments of labour, in addition
to those things that are used for directly transferring labour to its subject,
and which therefore, in one way or another, serve as conductors of activity, all
such objects as are necessary for carrying on the labour-process. These do not
enter directly into the process, but without them it is either impossible for it
to take place at all, or possible only to a partial extent. Once more we find
the earth to be a universal instrument of this sort, for it furnishes a locus
standi to the labourer and a field of employment for his activity. Among
instruments that are the result of previous labour and also belong to this
class, we find workshops, canals, roads, and so forth.
In the labour-process, therefore, man's activity, with the help of the
instruments of labour, effects an alteration, designed from the commencement, in
the material worked upon. The process disappears in the product, the latter is a
use-value, Nature's material adapted by a change of form to the wants of man.
Labour has incorporated itself with its subject: the former is materialised, the
latter transformed. That which in the labourer appeared as movement, now appears
in the product as a fixed quality without motion. The blacksmith forges and the
product is a forging.
If we examine the whole process from the point of view of its result, the
product, it is plain that both the instruments and the subject of labour, are
means of production, [6]
and that the labour itself is productive labour. [7]
Though a use-value, in the form of a product, issues from the labour-process,
yet other use-values, products of previous labour, enter into it as means of
production. The same-use-value is both the product of a previous process, and a
means of production in a later process. Products are therefore not only results,
but also essential conditions of labour.
With the exception of the extractive industries, in which the material for
labour is provided immediately by Nature, such as mining, hunting, fishing, and
agriculture (so far as the latter is confined to breaking up virgin soil), all
branches of industry manipulate raw material, objects already filtered through
labour, already products of labour. Such is seed in agriculture. Animals and
plants, which we are accustomed to consider as products of Nature, are in their
present form, not only products of, say last year's labour, but the result of a
gradual transformation, continued through many generations, under man's
superintendence, and by means of his labour. But in the great majority of cases,
instruments of labour show even to the most superficial observer, traces of the
labour of past ages.
Raw material may either form the principal substance of a product, or it may
enter into its formation only as an accessory. An accessory may be consumed by
the instruments of labour, as coal under a boiler, oil by a wheel, hay by
draft-horses, or it may be mixed with the raw material in order to produce some
modification thereof, as chlorine into unbleached linen, coal with iron,
dye-stuff with wool, or again, it may help to carry on the work itself, as in
the case of the materials used for heating and lighting workshops. The
distinction between principal substance and accessory vanishes in the true
chemical industries, because there none of the raw material re-appears, in its
original composition, in the substance of the product. [8]
Every object possesses various properties, and is thus capable of being
applied to different uses. One and the same product may therefore serve as raw
material in very different processes. Corn, for example, is a raw material for
millers, starch-manufacturers, distillers, and cattlebreeders. It also enters as
raw material into its own production in the shape of seed; coal, too, is at the
same time the product of, and a means of production in, coal-mining.
Again, a particular product may be used in one and the same process, both as
an instrument of labour and as raw material. Take, for instance, the fattening
of cattle, where the animal is the raw material, and at the same time an
instrument for the production of manure.
A product, though ready for immediate consumption, may yet serve as raw
material for a further product, as grapes when they become the raw material for
wine. On the other hand, labour may give us its product in such a form, that we
can use it only a's raw material, as is the case with Hence we see, that whether a use-value is to be regarded as raw material, as
instrument of labour, or as product, this is determined entirely by its function
in the labour-process, by the position it there occupies: as this varies, so
does its character.
Whenever therefore a product enters as a means of production into a new
labour-process, it thereby loses its character of product, and becomes a mere
factor in the process. A spinner treats spindles only as implements for
spinning, and flax only as the material that he spins. Of course it is
impossible to spin without material and spindles; and therefore the existence of
these things as products, at the commencement of the spinning operation, must be
presumed: but in the process itself, the fact that they are products of previous
labour, is a matter of utter indifference; just as in the digestive process, it
is of no importance whatever, that bread is the produce of the previous labour
of the farmer, the miller, and the baker. On the contrary, it is generally by
their imperfections as products, that the means of production in any process
assert themselves in their character of products. A blunt knife or weak thread
forcibly remind us of Mr. A., the cutler, or Mr. B., the spinner. In the
finished product the labour by means of which it has acquired its useful
qualities is not palpable, has apparently vanished.
A machine which does not serve the purposes of labour, is useless. In
addition, it falls a prey to the destructive influence of natural forces. Iron
rusts and wood rots. Yarn with which we neither weave nor knit, is cotton
wasted. Living labour must seize upon these things and rouse them from their
death-sleep, change them from mere possible use-values into real and effective
ones. Bathed in the fire of labour, appropriated as part and parcel of labour's
organism, and, as it were, made alive for the performance of their functions in
the process, they are in truth consumed, but consumed with a purpose, as
elementary constituents of new use-values, of new products, ever ready as means
of subsistence for individual consumption, or as means of production for some
new labour-process.
If then, on the one hand, finished products are not only results, but also
necessary conditions, of the labour-process, on the other hand, their assumption
into that process, their contact with living labour, is the sole means by which
they can be made to retain their character of use-values, and be utilised.
In so far then, as its instruments and subjects are themselves products,
labour consumes products in order to create products, or in other words,
consumes one set of products by turning them into means of production for
another set. But, just as in the beginning, the only participators in the
labour-process were man and the earth, which latter exists independently of man,
so even now we still employ in the process many means of production, provided
directly by Nature, that do not represent any combination of natural substances
with human labour.
The labour-process, resolved as above into its simple elementary factors, is
human action with a view to the production of use-values, appropriation of
natural substances to human requirements; it is the necessary condition for
effecting exchange of matter between man and Nature; it is the everlasting
Nature-imposed condition of human existence, and therefore is independent of
every social phase of that existence, or rather, is common to every such phase.
It was, therefore, not necessary to represent our labourer in connexion with
other labourers; man and his labour on one side, Nature and its materials on the
other, sufficed. As the taste of the porridge does not tell you who grew the
oats, no more does this simple process tell you of itself what are the social
conditions under which it is taking place, whether under the slave-owner's
brutal lash, or the anxious eye of the capitalist, whether Cincinnatus carries
it on in tilling his modest farm or a savage in killing wild animals with
stones. [9]
Let us now return to our would-be capitalist. We left him just after he had
purchased, in the open market, all the necessary factors of the labour-process-
its objective factors, the means of production, as well as its subjective
factor, labour-power. With the keen eye of an expert, he has selected the means
of production and the kind of labour-power best adapted to his particular trade,
be it spinning, bootmaking, or The labour-process, turned into the process by which the capitalist consumes
labour-power, exhibits two characteristic phenomena. First, the labourer works
under the control of the capitalist to whom his labour belongs; the capitalist
taking good care that the work is done in a proper manner, and that the means of
production are used with intelligence, so that there is no unnecessary waste of
raw material, and no wear and tear of the implements beyond what is necessarily
caused by the work.
Secondly, the product is the property of the capitalist and not that of the
labourer, its immediate producer. Suppose that a capitalist pays for a day's
labour-power at its value; then the right to use that power for a day belongs to
him, just as much as the right to use any other commodity, such as a horse that
he has hired for the day. To the purchaser of a commodity belongs its use, and
the seller of labour-power, by giving his labour, does no more, in reality, than
part with the use-value that he has sold. From the instant he steps into the
workshop, the use-value of his labour-power, and therefore also its use, which
is labour, belongs to the capitalist. By the purchase of labour-power, the
capitalist incorporates labour, as a living ferment, with the lifeless
constituents of the product. From his point of view, the labour-process is
nothing more than the consumption of the commodity purchased, i. e., of
labour-power; but this consumption cannot be effected except by supplying the
labour-power with the means of production. The labour-process is a process
between things that the capitalist has purchased, things that have become his
property. The product of this process belongs, therefore, to him, just as much
as does the wine which is the product of a process of fermentation completed in
his cellar. [10]
It must be borne in mind, that we are now dealing with the production of
commodities, and that, up to this point, we have only considered one aspect of
the process. Just as commodities are, at the same time, use-values and values,
so the process of producing them must be a labour-process, and at the same time,
a process of creating value. [11]
Let us now examine production as a creation of value.
We know that the value of each commodity is determined by the quantity of
labour expended on and materialised in it, by the working-time necessary, under
given social conditions, for its production. This rule also holds good in the
case of the product that accrued to our capitalist, as the result of the
labour-process carried on for him. Assuming this For spinning the yarn, raw material is required; suppose in this case 10 lbs.
of cotton. We have no need at present to investigate the value of this cotton,
for our capitalist has, we will assume, bought it at its full value, say of ten
shillings. In this price the labour required for the production of the cotton is
already expressed in terms of the average labour of society. We will further
assume that the wear and tear of the spindle, which, for our present purpose,
may represent all other instruments of labour employed, amounts to the value of
2s. If, then, twenty-four hours' labour, or two working-days, are required to
produce the quantity of gold represented by twelve shillings, we have here, to
begin with, two days' labour already incorporated in the yarn.
We must not let ourselves be misled by the circumstance that the cotton has
taken a new shape while the substance of the spindle has to a certain extent
been used up. By the general law of value, if the value of 40 lbs. of yarn = the
value of 40 lbs. of cotton + the value of a whole spindle, i. e., if the
same working-time is required to produce the commodities on either side of this
equation, then 10 lbs. of yarn are an equivalent for 10 lbs. of cotton, together
with one-fourth of a spindle. In the case we are considering the same
working-time is materialised in the 10 lbs. of yarn on the one hand, and in the
10 lbs. of cotton and the fraction of a spindle on the other. Therefore, whether
value appears in cotton, in a spindle, or in yarn, makes no difference in the
amount of that value. The spindle and cotton, instead of resting quietly side by
side, join together in the process, their forms are altered, and they are turned
into yarn; but their value is no more affected by this fact than it would be if
they had been simply exchanged for their equivalent in yarn.
The labour required for the production of the cotton, the raw material of the
yarn, is part of the labour necessary to produce the yarn, and is therefore
contained in the yarn. The same applies to the labour embodied in the spindle,
without whose wear and tear the cotton could not be spun.
Hence, in determining the value of the yarn, or the labour-time required for
its production, all the special processes carried on at various times and in
different places, which were necessary, first to produce the cotton and the
wasted portion of the spindle, and then with the cotton and spindle to spin the
yarn, may together be looked on as different and successive phases of one and
the same process. The whole of the labour in the yarn is past labour; and it is
a matter of no importance that the operations necessary for the production of
its constituent elements were carried on at times which, referred to the
present, are more remote than the final operation of spinning. If a definite
quantity The values of the means of production, i. e., the cotton and the
spindle, which values are expressed in the price of twelve shillings, are
therefore constituent parts of the value of the yarn, or, in other words, of the
value of the product.
Two conditions must nevertheless be fulfilled. First, the cotton and spindle
must concur in the production of a use-value; they must in the present case
become yarn. Value is independent of the particular use-value by which it is
borne, but it must be embodied in a use-value of some kind. Secondly, the time
occupied in the labour of production must not exceed the time really necessary
under the given social conditions of the case. Therefore, if no more than I lb.
of cotton be requisite to spin 11 lbs. of yarn, care must be taken that no more
than this weight of cotton is consumed in the production of 11 lbs. of yarn; and
similarly with regard to the spindle. Though the capitalist have a hobby, and
use a gold instead of a steel spindle, yet the only labour that counts for
anything in the value of the yarn is that which would be required to produce a
steel spindle, because no more is necessary under the given social conditions.
We now know what portion of the value of the yarn is owing to the cotton and
the spindle. It amounts to twelve shillings or the value of two days' work. The
next point for our consideration is, what portion of the value of the yarn is
added to the cotton by the labour of the spinner.
We have now to consider this labour under a very different aspect from that
which it had during the labour-process; there, we viewed it solely as that
particular kind of human activity which changes cotton into yarn; there, the
more the labour was suited to the work, the better the yarn, other circumstances
remaining the same. The labour of the spinner was then viewed as specifically
different from other kinds of productive labour, different on the one hand in
its speciaI aim, viz., spinning, different, on the other hand, in the special
character of its operations, in the special nature of its means of production
and in the special use-value of its product. For the operation of spinning,
cotton and spindles are a necessity, but for making rifled cannon they would be
of no use whatever. Here, on the contrary, where we consider the labour of the
spinner only so far as it is value-creating, i.e., a source of value, his
labour differs
in no respect from the labour of the man who bores cannon, or (what here
more nearly concerns us), from the labour of the cotton-planter and
spindle-maker incorporated in the means of production. It is solely by reason of
this identity, that cotton planting, spindle making and spinning, are capable of
forming the component parts differing only quantitatively from each other, of
one whole, namely, the value of the yarn. Here, we have nothing more to do with
the quality, the nature and the specific character of the labour, but merely
with its quantity. And this simply requires to be calculated. We proceed upon
the assumption that spinning is simple, unskilled labour, the average labour of
a given state of society. Hereafter we shall see that the contrary assumption
would make no difference.
While the labourer is at work, his labour constantly undergoes a
transformation: from being motion, it becomes an object without motion; from
being the labourer working, it becomes the thing produced. At the end of one
hour's spinning, that act is represented by a definite quantity of yarn; in
other words, a definite quantity of labour, namely that of one hour, has become
embodied in the cotton. We say labour, i.e., the expenditure of his vital
force by the spinner, and not spinning labour, because the special work of
spinning counts here, only so far as it is the expenditure of labour-power in
general, and not in so far as it is the specific work of the spinner.
In the process we are now considering it is of extreme importance, that no
more time be consumed in the work of transforming the cotton into yarn than is
necessary under the given social conditions. If under normal, i.e.,
average social conditions of production, a pounds of cotton ought to be
made into b pounds of yarn by one hour's labour, then a day's labour does
not count as 12 hours' labour unless 12 a pounds of cotton have been made
into 12 b pounds of yarn; for in the creation of value, the time that is
socially necessary alone counts.
Not only the labour, but also the raw material and the product now appear in
quite a new light, very different from that in which we viewed them in the
labour-process pure and simple. The raw material serves now merely as an
absorbent of a definite quantity of labour. By this absorption it is in fact
changed into yarn, because it is spun, because labour-power in the form of
spinning is added to it; but the product, the yarn, is now nothing more than a
measure of the labour absorbed by the cotton. If in one hour 1 2/3 lbs. of
cotton can be spun into 1 2/3 lbs. of yarn, then 10 lbs. of yarn indicate the
absorption of 6 hours' labour. Definite quantities of product, these quantities
being determined by experience, now represent nothing but definite quantities of
labour, definite masses of crystallised labour-time. They are nothing more
We are here no more concerned about the facts, that the labour is the
specific work of spinning, that its subject is cotton and its product yarn, than
we are about the fact that the subject itself is already a product and therefore
raw material. If the spinner, instead of spinning, were working in a coal mine,
the subject of his labour, the coal, would be supplied by Nature; nevertheless,
a definite quantity of extracted coal, a hundredweight for example, would
represent a definite quantity of absorbed labour.
We assumed, on the occasion of its sale, that the value of a day's
labour-power is three shillings, and that six hours' labour is incorporated in
that sum; and consequently that this amount of labour is requisite to produce
the necessaries of life daily required on an average by the labourer. If now our
spinner by working for one hour, can convert 1 2/3 lbs. of cotton into 1 2/3
lbs. of yarn, [12]
it follows that in six hours he will convert 10 lbs. of cotton into 10 lbs. of
yarn. Hence, during the spinning process, the cotton absorbs six hours' labour.
The same quantity of labour is also embodied in a piece of gold of the value of
three shillings. Consequently by the mere labour of spinning, a value of three
shillings is added to the cotton.
Let us now consider the total value of the product, the 10 lbs. of yarn. Two
and a half days' labour has been embodied in it, of which two days were
contained in the cotton and in the substance of the spindle worn away, and half
a day was absorbed during the process of spinning. This two and a half days'
labour is also represented by a piece of gold of the value of fifteen shillings.
Hence, fifteen shillings is an adequate price for the 10 lbs. of yarn, or the
price of one pound is eighteenpence.
Our capitalist stares in astonishment. The value of the product is exactly
equaI to the value of the capital advanced. The value so advanced has not
expanded, no surplus-value has been created, and consequently money has not been
converted into capital. The price of the yarn is fifteen shillings, and fifteen
shillings were spent in the open market upon the constituent elements of the
product, or, what amounts to the same thing, upon the factors of the
labour-process; ten shillings were paid for the cotton, two shillings for the
substance of the spindle worn away, and three shillings for the labour-power.
The swollen value of the yarn is of no avail, for it is merely the sum of the
values formerly existing in the cotton, the spindle, and the labour-power: out
of such There is in reality nothing very strange in this result. The value of one
pound of yarn being eighteenpence, if our capitalist buys 10 lbs. of yarn in the
market, he must pay fifteen shillings for them. It is clear that, whether a man
buys his house ready built, or gets it built for him, in neither case will the
mode of acquisition increase the amount of money laid out on the house.
Our capitalist, who is at home in his vulgar economy, exclaims: "Oh! but I
advanced my money for the express purpose of making more money." The way to
Hell is paved with good intentions, and he might just as easily have intended to
make money, without producing at all. [14]
He threatens all sorts of things. He won't be caught napping again. In future he
will buy the commodities in the market, instead of manufacturing them himself.
But if all his brother capitalists were to do the same, where would he find his
commodities in the market? And his money he cannot eat. He tries persuasion.
"Consider my abstinence; I might have played ducks and drakes with the 15
shillings; but instead of that I consumed it productively, and made yarn with
it." Very well, and by way of reward he is now in possession of good yarn
instead of a bad conscience; and as for playing the part of a miser, it would
never do for him to relapse into such bad ways as that; we have seen before to
what results such asceticism leads. Besides, where nothing is, the king has lost
his rights; whatever may be the merit of his abstinence, there is nothing
wherewith specially to remunerate it, because the value of the product is merely
the sum of the values of the commodities that were thrown into the process of
production. Let him therefore console' himself with the reflection that virtue
is its own reward, But no, he becomes importunate. He says: "The yarn is of
no use to me: I produced it for sale." In that case let him sell it, or,
still better, let him for Let us examine the matter more closely. The value of a day's
labour- Our capitalist foresaw this state of things, and that was the cause of his
laughter. The labourer therefore finds, in the workshop, the means of production
necessary for working, not only during six, but during twelve hours. Just as
during the six hours' process our 10 lbs. of cotton absorbed six hours' labour,
and became 10 lbs. of yarn, so now, 20 lbs. of cotton will absorb 12 hours'
labour and be changed into 20 lbs. of yarn. Let us now examine the product of
this prolonged process. There is now materialised in this 20 lbs. of yarn the
labour of five days, of Every condition of the problem is satisfied, while the laws that regulate the
exchange of commodities, have been in no way violated. Equivalent has been
exchanged for equivalent. For the capitalist as buyer paid for each commodity,
for the cotton, the spindle and the labour-power, its full value. He then did
what is done by every purchaser of commodities; he consumed their use-value. The
consumption of the labour-power, which was also the process of producing
commodities, resulted in 20 lbs. of yarn, having a value of 30 shillings. The
capitalist, formerly a buyer, now returns to market as a seller, of commodities.
He sells his yarn at eighteenpence a pound, which is its exact value. Yet for
all that he withdraws 3 shillings more from circulation than he originally threw
into it. This metamorphosis, this conversion of money into capital, takes place
both within the sphere of circulation and also outside it; within the
circulation, because conditioned by the purchase of the labour-power in the
market; outside the circulation, because what is done within it is only a
stepping-stone to the production of surplus-value, a process which is entirely
confined to the sphere of production. Thus "tout est pour le mieux dans le
meflleur des mondes possibles."
By turning his money into commodities that serve as the material elements of
a new product, and as factors in the labour-process, by incorporating living
labour with their dead substance, the capitalist at the same time converts
value, i.e., past, materialised, and dead labour into capital, into value
big with value, a live monster that is fruitful and multiplies.
If we now compare the two processes of producing value and of creating
surplus-value, we see that the latter is nothing but the continuation of the
former beyond a definite point. If on the one hand the process be not carried
beyond the point, where the value paid by the capitalist for the labour-power is
replaced by an exact equivalent, it is simply a process of producing value; if,
on the other hand, it be con If we proceed further, and compare the process of producing value with the
labour-process, pure and simple, we find that the latter consists of the useful
labour, the work, that produces use-values. Here we contemplate the labour as
producing a particular article; we view it under its qualitative aspect alone,
with regard to its end and aim. But viewed as a value-creating process, the same
labour-process presents itself under its quantitative aspect alone. Here it is a
question merely of the time occupied by the labourer in doing the work; of the
period during which the labour-power is usefully expended. Here, the commodities
that take part in the process, do not count any longer as necessary adjuncts of
labour-power in the production of a definite, useful object. They count merely
as depositories of so much absorbed or materialised labour; that labour, whether
previously embodied in the means of production, or incorporated in them for the
first time during the process by the action of labour-power, counts in either
case only according to its duration; it amounts to so many hours or days as the
case may be.
Moreover, only so much of the time spent in the production of any article is
counted, as, under the given social conditions, is necessary. The consequences
of this are various. In the first place, it becomes necessary that the labour
should be carried on under normal conditions. If a self-acting mule is the
implement in general use for spinning, it would be absurd to supply the spinner
with a distaff and spinning wheel. The cotton too must not be such rubbish as to
cause extra waste in being worked, but must be of suitable quality. Otherwise
the spinner would be found to spend more time in producing a pound of yarn than
is socially necessary, in which case the excess of time would create neither
value nor money. But whether the material factors of the process are of normal
quality or not, depends not upon the labourer, but entirely upon the capitalist.
Then again, the labour-power itself must be of average efficacy. In the trade in
which it is being employed, it must possess the average skill, handiness and
quickness prevalent in that trade, and our capitalist took good care to buy
labour-power of such normal goodness. This power must be applied with the
average amount of exertion and with the usual degree of intensity; and the
capitalist is as careful to see that this is done, as that his workmen are not
idle for a single moment. He has bought, the use of the labour-power for a
definite period, and he insists upon his rights. He has no intention of being
robbed. Lastly, and for this purpose our friend has a penal code of his own, all
wasteful consumption of raw material or instruments of labour is strictly
forbidden, because what is so wasted, represents We now see, that the difference between labour, considered on the one hand as
producing utilities, and on the other hand, as creating value, a difference
which we discovered by our analysis of a commodity, resolves itself into a
distinction between two aspects of the process of production.
The process of production, considered on the one hand as the unity of the
labour-process and the process of creating value, is production of commodities;
considered on the other hand as the unity of the labour-process and the process
of producing surplus-value, it is the capitalist process of production, or
capitalist production of commodities.
We stated, on a previous page, that in the creation of surplus-value it does
not in the least matter, whether the labour appropriated by the capitalist be
simple unskilled labour of average quality or more complicated skilled labour.
All labour of a higher or more complicated character than average labour is
expenditure of labour-power of a more costly kind, labour-power whose production
has cost more time and labour, and which therefore has a higher value, than
unskilled or But on the other hand, in every process of creating value, the reduction of
skilled labour to average social labour, e.g., one day of skilled to six
days of unskilled labour, is unavoidable. [19]
We therefore save ourselves a superfluous operation, and simplify our analysis,
by the assumption, that the labour of the workman employed by the capitalist is
unskilled average labour.
[1] "The earth's spontaneous productions being in small
quantity, and quite independent of man, appear, as it were, to be furnished by
Nature, in the same way as a small sum is given to a young man, in order to put
him in a way of industry, and of making his fortune." (James Stueart:
"Principles of Polit. Econ." edit. Dublin, 1770, v. I, p.116.)
[2] "Reason is just as cunning as she is powerful. Her
cunning consists principally in her mediating activity, which, by causing
objects to act and re-act on each other in accordance with their own nature, in
this way, without any direct interference in the process, carries out reason's
intentions." (Hegel: "Enzyklopädie, Erster Theil, Die Logik," Berlin, 1840, p.
382.)
[3] In his otherwise miserable work ("Théorie de I'Econ.
Polit." Paris, 1815), Ganilh enumerates in a striking manner in opposition to
the "Physiocrats" the long series of previous processes necessary before
agriculture properly so called can commence.
[4] Turgot in his "Réflexions sur la Formation et la
Distribution des Richesses" (1766) brings well into prominence the importance of
domesticated animals to early civilisation.
[5] The least important commodities of all for the
technological comparison of different epochs of production are articles of
luxury, in the strict meaning of the term. However little our written histories
up to this time notice the development of material production, which is the
basis of all social life, and therefore of all real history, yet prehistoric
times have been classified in accordance with the results, not of so-called
historical, but of materialistic investigations. These periods have been
divided, to correspond with the materials from which their implements and
weapons were made, viz., into the stone, the bronze, and the iron ages.
[6] It appears paradoxical to assert, that uncaught fish,
for instance, are a means of production in the fishing industry. But hitherto no
one has discovered the art of catching fish in waters that contain none.
[7] This method of determining, from the standpoint of the
labour-process alone, what is productive labour, is by no means directly
applicable to the case of the capitalist process of production.
[8] Storch calls true raw materials "matières," and
accessory material "matériaux." Cherbuliez describes accessories as "matières
instrumentales."
[9] By a wonderful fcat of logical acumen, Colonel Torrens
has discovered, in this stone of the savage the origin of capital. "In the first
stone which he [the savage] flings at the wild animal he pursues, in the first
stick that he seizes to strike down the fruit which hangs above his reach, we
see the appropriation of one article for the purpose of aiding in the
acquisition of another, and thus discover the origin of capital." (R. Torrens:
"An Essay on the Production of Wealth," &c., pp. 70-71.)
[10] "Products are appropriated before they are converted
into capital; this conversion does not secure them from such appropriation."
(Cheibuliez: "Richesse on Pauvreté," edit. Paris, 1841, p. 54.) "The
Proletarian, by selling his labour for a definite quantity of the necessaries of
life, renounces all claim to a share in the product. The mode of appropriation
of the products remains the same as before; it is in no way altered by the
bargain we have mentioned. The product belongs exclusively to the capitalist,
who supplied the raw material and the necessaries of life; and this is a
rigorous consequence of the law of appropriation, a law whose fundamental
principle was the very opposite, namely, that every labourer has an exclusive
right to the ownership of what he produces." (l. c., p. 58.) "When the labourers
receive wages for their labour ... the capitalist is then the owner not of the
capital only" (he means the means of production) "but of the labour also. If
what is paid as wages is included, as it commonly is, in the term capital, it is
absurd to talk of labour separately from capital. The word capital as thus
employed includes labour and capital both." (James Mill: "Elements of Pol.
Econ.," &c., Ed. 1821, pp. 70, 71.)
[11] As has been stated in a previous note, the English
language has two different expressions for these two different aspects of
labour: in the Simple Labour-process, the process of producing Use-Values, it is
Work; in the process of creation of Value, it is Labour, taking
the term in its strictly economic sense. -- F. E.
[12] These figures are quite arbitrary.
[13] This is the fundamental proposition on which is based
the doctrine of the Physiocrats as to the unproductiveness of all labour that is
not agriculture: it is irrefutable for the orthodox economist. "Cette façon
d'imputer à une seule chose la valeur de plusieurs autres" (par exemple au lin
la consommation du tisserand), "d'appliquer, pour ainsi dire, couche sur couche,
plusieurs valcurs sur une seule, fait que celle-ci grossit d'autant.... Le terme
d'addition peint trés-bien la maniere dont se forme le prix des ouvrages de
maind'oeuvre; ce prix n'est qu'un total de plusieurs valeurs consommées et
additionnées ensemble; or, additionner n'est pas multiplier." ("Mercier de la
Rivière," l. c., p. 599.)
[14] Thus from 1844-47 he withdrew part of his capital
from productive employment, in order to throw it away in railway speculations;
and so also, during the American Civil War, he closed his factory, and turned
his work-people into the streets, in order to gamble on the Liverpool cotton
exchange.
[15] "Extol thyself, put on finery and adorn thyself ...
but whoever takes more or better than he gives, that is usury, and is not
service, but wrong done to his neighbour, as when one steals and robs. All is
not service and benefit to a neighbour that is called service and benefit. For
an adulteress and adulterer do one another great service and pleasure. A
horseman does an incendiary a great service, by helping him to rob on the
highway, and pillage land and houses. The papists do ours a great service, in
that they don't drown, burn, murder all of them, or let them all rot in prison;
but let some live, and only drive them out, or take from them what they have.
The devil himself does his servants inestimable service.... To sum up, the world
is full of great, excellent, and daily service and benefit." (Martin Luther: "An
die Pfarrherrn wider den Wucher zu predigen," Wittenberg, 1540.)
[16] In "Zur Kritik der Pol. Oek.," p. 14, I make the
following remark on this point -- "It is not difficult to understand what
'service' the category 'service' must render to a class of economists like J. B.
Say and F. Bastiat."
[17] This is one of the circumstances that makes
production by slave labour such a costly process. The labourer here is, to use a
striking expression of the ancients, distinguishable only as instrumentum
vocale, from an animal as instrumentum semi-vocale, and from an implement as
instrumentum mutum. But he himself takes care to let both beast and implement
feel that he is none of them,'but is a man. He convinces himself with immense
satisfaction, that he is a different being, by treating the one unmercifully and
damaging the other con amore. Hence the principle, univerially applied in this
method of production, only to employ the rudest and heaviest implements and such
as are difficult to damage owing to their sheer clumsiness. In the slave-statcs
bordering on the Gulf of Mexico, down to the date of the civil war, ploughs
constructed on old Chinese models, which turned up the soil like a hog or a
mole, instead of making furrows, were alone to be found. Conf. J. E. Cairnes.
"The Slave Power," London, 1862, p. 46 sqq. In his "Sea Board Slave States,"
Olmsted tells us: "I am here shown tools that no man in his senses, with us,
would allow a labourcr, for whom he was paying wages, to be encumbered with; and
the excessive weight and clumsiness of which, I would judge, would make work at
least ten per cent greater than with those ordinarily used with us. And I am
assured that, in the careless and clumsy way they must be used by the slaves,
anything lighter or less rude could not be fumished them with good economy, and
that such tools as we constantly give our labourers and find our profit in
giving them, would not last out a day in a Virginia comficid-much lighter and
more free from stones though it be than ours. So, too, when I ask why mules are
so universally substituted for horses on the farm, the first reason given, and
confessedly the most conclusive one, is that horses cannot bear the treatment
that they always must get from negroes; horses are always soon foundered or
crippled by them, while mules will bear cudgelling, or lose a meal or two now
and then, and not be materially injured, and they do not take cold or get sick,
if neglected or overworked. But I do not need to go further than to the window
of the room in which I am writing, to see at almost any time, treatment of
cattle that would ensure the immediate discharge of the driver by almost any
farmer owning them in the North."
[18] The distinction between skilled and unskilled labour
rests in part on pure illusion, or, to say the least, on distinctions that have
long since ceased to be real, and that survive only by virtue of a traditional
convention; in part on the helpless condition of some groups of the
working-class, a condition that prevents themfrom exacting equally with the rest
the value of their labour-power. Accidental circumstances here play so great a
part, that these two forms of labour sometimes change places. Where, for
instance, the physique of the working-class has deteriorated, and is, relatively
speaking, exhausted, which in the case in all countries with a well developed
capitalist production, the lower forms of labour, which demand great expenditure
of muscle, are in general considered as skilled, compared with much more
delicate forms of labour; the latter sink down to the level of unskilled labour.
Take as an example the labour of a bricklayer, which in England occupies a much
higher level than that of a damask-weaver. Again, although the labour of a
fustian cutter demands great bodily exertion, and is at the same time unhealthy,
yet it counts only as unskilled labour. And then, we must not forget, that the
so-called skilled labour does not occupy a large space in the field of national
labour. Laing estimates that in England (and Wales) the livelihood of 11,300,000
people depends on unskilled labour. If from the total population of 18,000,000
living at the time when he wrote, we deduct 1,000,000 for the "genteel
population," and 1,500,000 for paupers, vagrants, criminals, prostitutes,
&c., and 4,650,000 who compose the middle-class, there remain the above
mentioned 11,000,000. But in his middle-class he includes people that live on
the interest of small investments, officials, men of letters, artists,
schoolmasters and the like, and in order to swell the number he also includes in
these 4,650,000 the better paid portioti of the factory operatives! The
bricklayers, too, figure amongst them. (S. Laing: "National Distress," &c.,
London, 1844). "The great class who have nothing to give for food but ordinary
labour, are the great bulk of the people." (James Mill, in art.:"Colony,"
Supplement to the Encyclop. Brit., 1831.)
[19] "Where reference is made to labour as a measure of
value, it necessarily implies labour of one particular kind ... the proportion
which the other kinds bear to it being easily ascertained." ("Outlines of Pol.
Econ.," Lond., 1832, pp. 22 and 23.)
Transcribed for the Internet by zodiac@interlog.com
THE PRODUCTION OF SURPLUS-VALUE
NOTES
On to
chapter 8
Capital, vol.
1
Table of contents
Marx/Engels
Internet Library
Marx/Engels
Internet Archive