part I |
CHAPTER
I |
The wealth of those societies in which the capitalist mode of production prevails, presents itself as "an immense accumulation of commodities," [1] its unit being a single commodity. Our investigation must therefore begin with the analysis of a commodity.
A commodity is, in the first place, an object outside us, a thing that by its properties satisfies human wants of some sort or another. The nature of such wants, whether, for instance, they spring from the stomach or from fancy, makes no difference. [2] Neither are we here concerned to know how the object satisfies these wants, whether directly as means of subsistence, or indirectly as means of production.
Every useful thing, as iron, paper, &c., may be looked at from the two points of view of quality and quantity. It is an assemblage of many properties, and may therefore be of use in various ways. To discover the various uses of things is the work of history. [3] So also is the establishment of socially-recognized standards of measure for the quantities of these useful objects. The diversity of these measures has its origin partly in the diverse nature of the objects to be measured, partly in convention.
The utility of a thing makes it a use-value. [4] But this utility is not a thing of air. Being limited by the physical properties of the commodity, it has no existence apart from that commodity. A commodity, such as iron, corn, or a diamond, is therefore, so far as it is a material thing, a use-value, something useful. This property of a commodity is independent of the amount of labour required to appropriate its useful qualities. When treating of use-value, we always assume to be dealing with definite quantities, such as dozens of watches, yards of linen, or tons of iron. The use-values of commodities furnish the material for a special study, that of the commercial knowledge of commodities. [5] Use-values become a reality only by use or consumption: they also constitute the substance of all wealth, whatever may be the social form of that wealth. In the form of society we are about to consider, they are, in addition, the material depositories of exchange-value.
Exchange-value, at first sight, presents itself as a quantitative relation, as the proportion in which values in use of one sort are exchanged for those of another sort, [6] a relation constantly changing with time and place. Hence exchange-value appears to be something accidental and purely relative, and consequently an intrinsic value, i.e., an exchange-value that is inseparably connected with, inherent in commodities, seems a contradiction in terms. [7] Let us consider the matter a little more closely.
A given commodity, e.g., a quarter of wheat is exchanged for x blacking, y silk, or z gold, &c. -- in short, for other commodities in the most different proportions. Instead of one exchange-value, the wheat has, therefore, a great many. But since x blacking, y silk, or z gold &c., each represents the exchange-value of one quarter of wheat, x blacking, y silk, z gold, &c., must, as exchange-values, be replaceable by each other, or equal to each other. Therefore, first: the valid exchange-values of a given commodity express something equal; secondly, exchange-value, generally, is only the mode of expression, the phenomenal form, of something contained in it, yet distinguishable from it.
Let us take two commodities, e.g., corn and iron. The proportions in which they are exchangeable, whatever those proportions may be, can always be represented by an equation in which a given quantity of corn is equated to some quantity of iron: e.g., 1 quarter corn = x cwt. iron. What does this equation tell us? It tells us that in two different things -- in 1 quarter of corn and x cwt. of iron, there exists in equal quantities something common to both. The two things must therefore be equal to a third, which in itself is neither the one nor the other. Each of them, so far as it is exchange-value, must therefore be reducible to this third.
A simple geometrical illustration will make this clear. In order to calculate and compare the areas of rectilinear figures, we decompose them into triangles. But the area of the triangle itself is expressed by something totally different from its visible figure, namely, by half the product of the base multiplied by the altitude. In the same way the exchange-values of commodities must be capable of being expressed in terms of something common to them all, of which thing they represent a greater or less quantity.
This common "something" cannot be either a geometrical, a chemical, or any other natural property of commodities. Such properties claim our attention only in so far as they affect the utility of those commodities, make them use-values. But the exchange of commodities is evidently an act characterised by a total abstraction from use-value. Then one use-value is just as good as another, provided only it be present in sufficient quantity. Or, as old Barbon says, "one sort of wares are as good as another, if the values be equal. There is no difference or distinction in things of equal value.... An hundred pounds' worth of lead or iron, is of as great value as one hundred pounds' worth of silver or gold." [8] As use-values, commodities are, above all, of different qualities, but as exchange-values they are merely different quantities, and consequently do not contain an atom of use-value.
If then we leave out of consideration the use-value of commodities, they have only one common property left, that of being products of labour. But even the product of labour itself has undergone a change in our hands. If we make abstraction from its use-value, we make abstraction at the same time from the material elements and shapes that make the product a use-value; we see in it no longer a table, a house, yarn, or any other useful thing. Its existence as a material thing is put out of sight. Neither can it any longer be regarded as the product of the labour of the joiner, the mason, the spinner, or of any other definite kind of productive labour. Along with the useful qualities of the products themselves, we put out of sight both the useful character of the various kinds of labour embodied in them, and the concrete forms of that labour; there is nothing left but what is common to them all; all are reduced to one and the same sort of labour, human labour in the abstract.
Let us now consider the residue of each of these products; it consists of the same unsubstantial reality in each, a mere congelation of homogeneous human labour, of labour-power expended without regard to the mode of its expenditure. All that these things now tell us is, that human labour-power has been expended in their production, that human labour is embodied in them. When looked at as crystals of this social substance, common to them all, they are -- Values.
We have seen that when commodities are exchanged, their exchange-value manifests itself as something totally independent of their use-value. But if we abstract from their use-value, there remains their Value as defined above. Therefore, the common substance that manifests itself in the exchange-value of commodities, whenever they are exchanged, is their value. The progress of our investigation will show that exchange-value is the only form in which the value of commodities can manifest itself or be expressed. For the present, however, we have to consider the nature of value independently of this, its form.
A use-value, or useful article, therefore, has value only because human labour in the abstract has been embodied or materialised in it. How, then, is the magnitude of this value to be measured? Plainly, by the quantity of the value-creating substance, the labour, contained in the article. The quantity of labour, however, is measured by its duration, and labour-time in its turn finds its standard in weeks, days, and hours.
Some people might think that if the value of a commodity is determined by the quantity of labour spent on it, the more idle and unskilful the labourer, the more valuable would his commodity be, because more time would be required in its production. The labour, however, that forms the substance of value, is homogeneous human labour, expenditure of one uniform labour-power. The total labour-power of society, which is embodied in the sum total of the values of all commodities produced by that society, counts here as one homogeneous mass of human labour-power, composed though it be of innumerable individual units. Each of these units is the same as any other, so far as it has the character of the average labour-power of society, and takes effect as such; that is, so far as it requires for producing a commodity, no more time than is needed on an average, no more than is socially necessary. The labour-time socially necessary is that required to produce an article under the normal conditions of production, and with the average degree of skill and intensity prevalent at the time. The introduction of power-looms into England probably reduced by one-half the labour required to weave a given quantity of yarn into cloth. The hand-loom weavers, as a matter of fact, continued to require the same time as before; but for all that, the product of one hour of their labour represented after the change only half an hour's social labour, and consequently fell to one-half its former value.
We see then that that which determines the magnitude of the value of any article is the amount of labour socially necessary, or the labour-time socially necessary for its production. [9] Each individual commodity, in this connexion, is to be considered as an average sample of its class. [10] Commodities, therefore, in which equal quantities of labour are embodied, or which can be produced in the same time, have the same value. The value of one commodity is to the value of any other, as the labour-time necessary for the production of the one is to that necessary for the production of the other. "As values, all commodities are only definite masses of congealed labour-time." [11]
The value of a commodity would therefore remain constant, if the labour-time required for its production also remained constant. But the latter changes with every variation in the productiveness of labour. This productiveness is determined by various circumstances, amongst others, by the average amount of skill of the workmen, the state of science, and the degree of its practical application, the social organisation of production, the extent and capabilities of the means of production, and by physical conditions. For example, the same amount of labour in favourable seasons is embodied in 8 bushels of corn, and in unfavourable, only in four. The same labour extracts from rich mines more metal than from poor mines. Diamonds are of very rare occurrence on the earth's surface, and hence their discovery costs, on an average, a great deal of labour-time. Consequently much labour is represented in a small compass. Jacob doubts whether gold has ever been paid for at its full value. This applies still more to diamonds. According to Eschwege, the total produce of the Brazilian diamond mines for the eighty years, ending in 1823, had not realised the price of one and-a-half years' average produce of the sugar and coffee plantations of the same country, although the diamonds cost much more labour, and therefore represented more value. With richer mines, the same quantity of labour would embody itself in more diamonds, and their value would fall. If we could succeed at a small expenditure of labour, in converting carbon into diamonds, their value might fall below that of bricks. In general, the greater the productiveness of labour, the less is the labour-time required for the production of an article, the less is the amount of labour crystallised in that article, and the less is its value; and vice versā, the less the productiveness of labour, the greater is the labour-time required for the production of an article, and the greater is its value. The value of a commodity, therefore, varies directly as the quantity, and inversely as the productiveness, of the labour incorporated in it.
A thing can be a use-value, without having value. This is the case whenever its utility to man is not due to labour. Such are air, virgin soil, natural meadows, &c. A thing can be useful, and the product of human labour, without being a commodity. Whoever directly satisfies his wants with the produce of his own labour, creates, indeed, use-values, but not commodities. In order to produce the latter, he must not only produce use-values, but use-values for others, social use-values. (And not only for others, without more. The mediaeval peasant produced quit-rent-corn for his feudal lord and tithe-corn for his parson. But neither the quit-rent-corn nor the tithe-corn became commodities by reason of the fact that they had been produced for others. To become a commodity a product must be transferred to another, whom it will serve as a use-value, by means of an exchange.) [12] Lastly nothing can have value, without being an object of utility. If the thing is useless, so is the labour contained in it; the labour does not count as labour, and therefore creates no value.
Let us take two commodities such as a coat and 10 yards of linen, and let the
former be double the value of the latter, so that, if 10 yards of linen = W, the
coat = 2W.
The coat is a use-value that satisfies a particular want. Its existence is
the result of a special sort of productive activity, the nature of which is
determined by its aim, mode of operation, subject, means, and result. The
labour, whose utility is thus represented by the value in use of its product, or
which manifests itself by making its product a use-value, we call useful labour
In this connexion we consider only its useful effect.
As the coat and the linen are two qualitatively different use-values, so also
are the two forms of labour that produce them, tailoring and weaving. Were these
two objects not qualitatively different, not produced respectively by labour of
different quality, they could not stand to each other in the relation of
commodities. Coats are not exchanged for coats, one use-value is not exchanged
for another of the same kind.
To all the different varieties of values in use there correspond as many
different kinds of useful labour, classified according to the order, genus,
species, and variety to which they belong in the social division of labour. This
division of labour is a necessary condition for the production of commodities,
but it does not follow, conversely, that the production of commodities is a
necessary condition for the division of labour. In the primitive Indian
community there is social division of labour, without production of commodities.
Or, to take an example nearer home, in every factory the labour is divided
according to a system, but this division is not brought about by the operatives
mutually exchanging their individual products. Only such products can become
commodities with regard to each other, as result from different kinds of labour,
each kind being carried on independently and for the account of private
individuals.
To resume, then: In the use-value of each commodity there is contained useful
labour, i.e., productive activity of a definite kind and exercised with a
definite aim. Use-values cannot confront each other as commodities, unless the
useful labour embodied in them is qualitatively different in each of them. In a
community, the produce of which in general takes the form of commodities,
i.e., in a community of commodity producers, this qualitative difference
between the useful forms of labour that are carried on independently of
individual producers, each on their own account, develops into a complex system,
a social division of labour.
Anyhow, whether the coat be worn by the tailor or by his customer, in either
case it operates as a use-value. Nor is the relation between the coat and the
labour that produced it altered by the circumstance that tailoring may have
become a special trade, an independent branch of the social division of labour.
Wherever the want of clothing forced them to it, the human race made clothes for
thousands of years, without a single man becoming a tailor. But coats and linen,
like every other element of material wealth that is not the spontaneous produce
of Nature, must invariably owe their existence to a special productive activity,
exercised with a definite aim, an activity that appropriates particular
nature-given materials to particular human wants. So far therefore as labour is
a creator of use-value, is useful labour, it is a necessary condition,
independent of all forms of society, for the existence of the human race; it is
an eternal nature-imposed necessity, without which there can be no material
exchanges between man and Nature, and therefore no life.
The use-values, coat, linen, &c., i.e., the bodies of commodities,
are combinations of two elements -- matter and labour. If we take away the
useful labour expended upon them, a material substratum is always left, which is
furnished by Nature without the help of man. The latter can work only as Nature
does, that is by changing the form of matter. [13]
Nay more, in this work of changing the form he is constantly helped by natural
forces. We see, then, that labour is not the only source of material wealth, of
use-values produced by labour. As William Petty puts it, labour is its father
and the earth its mother.
Let us now pass from the commodity considered as a use-value to the value of
commodities.
By our assumption, the coat is worth twice as much as the linen. But this is
a mere quantitative difference, which for the present does not concern us. We
bear in mind, however, that if the value of the coat is double that of 10 yds.
of linen, 20 yds. of linen must have the same value as one coat. So far as they
are values, the coat and the linen are things of a like substance, objective
expressions of essentially identical labour. But tailoring and weaving are,
qualitatively, different kinds of labour. There are, however, states of society
in which one and the same man does tailoring and weaving alternately, in which
case these two forms of labour are mere modifications of the labour of the same
individual, and no special and fixed functions of different persons, just as the
coat which our tailor makes one day, and the trousers which he makes another
day, imply only a variation in the labour of one and the same individual.
Moreover, we see at a glance that, in our capitalist society, a given portion of
human labour is, in accordance with the varying demand, at one time supplied in
the form of tailoring, at another in the form of weaving. This change may
possibly not take place without friction, but take place it must.
Productive activity, if we leave out of sight its special form, viz., the
useful character of the labour, is nothing but the expenditure of human
labour-power. Tailoring and weaving, though qualitatively different productive
activities, are each a productive expenditure of human brains, nerves, and
muscles, and in this sense are human labour. They are but two different modes of
expending human labour-power. Of course, this labour-power, which remains the
same under all its modifications, must have attained a certain pitch of
development before it can be expended in a multiplicity of modes. But the value
of a commodity represents human labour in the abstract, the expenditure of human
labour in general. And just as in society, a general or a banker plays a great
part, but mere man, on the other hand, a very shabby part, [14]
so here with mere human labour. It is the expenditure of simple labour-power,
i.e., of the labour-power which, on an average, apart from any special
development, exists in the organism of every ordinary individual. Simple average
labour, it is true, varies in character in different countries and at different
times, but in a particular society it is given. Skilled labour counts only as
simple labour intensified, or rather, as multiplied simple labour, a given
quantity of skilled being considered equal to a greater quantity of simple
labour. Experience shows that this reduction is constantly being made. A
commodity may be the product of the most skilled labour, but its value, by
equating it to the product of simple unskilled labour, represents a definite
quantity of the latter labour alone. [15]
The different proportions in which different sorts of labour are reduced to
unskilled labour as their standard. are established by a social process that
goes on behind the backs of the producers, and, consequently, appear to be fixed
by custom. For simplicity's sake we shall henceforth account every kind of
labour to be unskilled, simple labour; by this we do no more than save ourselves
the trouble of making the reduction.
Just as, therefore, in viewing the coat and linen as values, we abstract from
their different use-values, so it is with the labour represented by those
values: we disregard the difference between its useful forms, weaving and
tailoring. As the use-values, coat and linen, are combinations of special
productive activities with cloth and yarn, while the values, coat and linen,
are, on the other hand, mere homogeneous congelations of undifferentiated
labour, so the labour embodied in these latter values does not count by virtue
of its productive relation to cloth and yarn, but only as being expenditure of
human labour-power. Tailoring and weaving are necessary factors in the creation
of the use-values, coat and linen, precisely because these two kinds of labour
are of different qualities; but only in so far as abstraction is made from their
special qualities, only in so far as both possess the same quality of being
human labour, do tailoring and weaving form the substance of the values of the
same articles.
Coats and linen, however, are not merely values, but values of definite
magnitude, and according to our assumption, the coat is worth twice as much as
the ten yards of linen. Whence this difference in their values? It is owing to
the fact that the linen contains only half as much labour as the coat, and
consequently, that in the production of the latter, labour-power must have been
expended during twice the time necessary for the production of the former.
While, therefore, with reference to use-value, the labour contained in a
commodity counts only qualitatively, with reference to value it counts only
quantitatively, and must first be reduced to human labour pure and simple. In
the former case, it is a question of How and What, in the latter of How much?
How long a time? Since the magnitude of the value of a commodity represents only
the quantity of labour embodied in it, it follows that all commodities, when
taken in certain proportions, must be equal in value.
If the productive power of all the different sorts of useful labour required
for the production of a coat remains unchanged, the sum of the values of the
coats produced increases with their number. If one coat represents x days'
labour, two coats represent 2x days' labour, and so on. But assume that the
duration of the labour necessary for he production of a coat becomes doubled or
halved. In the first case one coat is worth as much as two coats were before; in
the second case, two coats are only worth as much as one was before, although in
both cases one coat renders the same service as before. and the useful labour
embodied in it remains of the same quality. But the quantity of labour spent on
its production has altered.
An increase in the quantity of use-values is an increase of material wealth.
With two coats two men can be clothed, with one coat only one man. Nevertheless,
an increased quantity of material wealth may correspond to a simultaneous fall
in the magnitude of its value. This antagonistic movement has its origin in the
two-fold character of labour. Productive power has reference, of course, only to
labour of some useful concrete form, the efficacy of any special productive
activity during a given time being dependent on its productiveness. Useful
labour becomes, therefore, a more or less abundant source of products, in
proportion to the rise or fall of its productiveness. On the other hand, no
change in this productiveness affects the labour represented by value. Since
productive power is an attribute of the concrete useful forms of labour, of
course it can no longer have any bearing on that labour, so soon as we make
abstraction from those concrete useful forms. However then productive power may
vary, the same labour, exercised during equal periods of time, always yields
equal amounts of value. But it will yield, during equal periods of time,
different quantities of values in use; more, if the productive power rise,
fewer, if it fall. The same change in productive power, which increases the
fruitfulness of labour, and, in consequence, the quantity of use-values produced
by that labour, will diminish the total value of this increased quantity of
use-values, provided such change shorten the total labour-time necessary for
their production; and vice versā.
On the one hand all labour is, speaking physiologically, an expenditure of
human labour-power, and in its character of identical abstract human labour, it
creates and forms the value of commodities. On the other hand, all labour is the
expenditure of human labour-power in a special form and with a definite aim, and
in this, its character of concrete useful labour, it produces use-values. [16]
The reality of the value of commodities differs in this respect from Dame
Quickly, that we don't know "where to have it." The value of commodities is the
very opposite of the coarse materiality of their substance, not an atom of
matter enters into its composition. Turn and examine a single commodity, by
itself, as we will, yet in so far as it remains an object of value, it seems
impossible to grasp it. If, however we bear in mind that the value of
commodities has a purely social reality, and that they acquire this reality only
in so far as they are expressions or embodiments of one identical social
substance, viz., human labour, it follows as a matter of course, that value can
only manifest itself in the social relation of commodity to commodity. In fact
we started from exchange-value, or the exchange relation of commodities, in
order to get at the value that lies hidden behind it. We must now return to this
form under which value first appeared to us.
Every one knows, if he knows nothing else, that commodities have a value-form
common to them all, and presenting a marked contrast with the varied bodily
forms of their use-values. I mean their money-form. Here, however, a task is set
us, the performance of which has never yet even been attempted by bourgeois
economy, the task of tracing the genesis of this money-form, of developing the
expression of value implied in the value-relation of commodities, from its
simplest, almost imperceptible outline, to the dazzling money-form. By doing
this we shall, at the same time, solve the riddle presented by money.
The simplest value-relation is evidently that of one commodity to some one
other commodity of a different kind. Hence the relation between the values of
two commodities supplies us with the simplest expression of the value of a
single commodity.
20 yards of linen = 1 coat, or Here two different kinds of commodities (in our example the linen and the
coat), evidently play two different parts. The linen expresses its value in the
coat; the coat serves as the material in which that value is expressed. The
former plays an active, the latter a passive, part. The value of the linen is
represented as relative value, or appears in relative form. The coat officiates
as equivalent, or appears in equivalent form.
The relative form and the equivalent form are two intimately connected,
mutually dependent and inseparable elements of the expression of value; but, at
the same time, are mutually exclusive, antagonistic extremes -- i.e.,
poles of the same expression. They are allotted respectively to the two
different commodities brought into relation by that expression. It is not
possible to express the value of linen in linen. 20 yards of linen = 20 yards of
linen is no expression of value. On the contrary, such an equation merely says
that 20 yards of linen are nothing else than 20 yards of linen, a definite
quantity of the use-value linen. The value of the linen can therefore be
expressed only relatively -- i.e., in some other commodity. The relative
form of the value of the linen pre-supposes, therefore, the presence of some
other commodity -- here the coat -- under the form of an equivalent. On the
other hand, the commodity that figures as the equivalent cannot at the same time
assume the relative form. That second commodity is not the one whose value is
expressed. Its function is merely to serve as the material in which the value of
the first commodity is expressed.
No doubt, the expression 20 yards of linen = 1 coat, or 20 yards of linen are
worth 1 coat, implies the opposite relation. 1 coat = 20 yards of linen, or 1
coat is worth 20 yards of linen. But, in that case, I must reverse the equation,
in order to express the value of the coat relatively; and. so soon as I do that
the linen becomes the equivalent instead of the coat. A single commodity cannot,
therefore, simultaneously assume, in the same expression of value, both forms.
The very polarity of these forms makes them mutually exclusive.
Whether, then, a commodity assumes the relative form, or the opposite
equivalent form, depends entirely upon its accidental position in the expression
of value -- that is, upon whether it is the commodity whose value is being
expressed or the commodity in which value is being expressed.
Whether 20 yards of linen = 1 coat or = 20 coats or = x coats-that is,
whether a given quantity of linen is worth few or many coats, every such
statement implies that the linen and coats, as magnitudes of value, are
expressions of the same unit, things of the same kind. Linen = coat is the basis
of the equation.
But the two commodities whose identity of quality is thus assumed, do not
play the same part. It is only the value of the linen that is expressed. And
how? By its reference to the coat as its equivalent, as something that can be
exchanged for it. In this relation the coat is the mode of existence of value,
is value embodied, for only as such is it the same as the linen. On the other
hand, the linen's own value comes to the front, receives independent expression,
for it is only as being value that it is comparable with the coat as a thing of
equal value, or exchangeable with the coat. To borrow an illustration from
chemistry, butyric acid is a different substance from propyl formate. Yet both
are made up of the same chemical substances, carbon (C), hydrogen (H), and
oxygen (O), and that, too, in like proportions -- namely, C4H8O2. If now we
equate butyric acid to propyl formate, then, in the first place, propyl formate
would be, in this relation, merely a form of existence of C4H8O2; and in the
second place, we should be stating that butyric acid also consists of C4H8O2.
Therefore, by thus equating the two substances, expression would be given to
their chemical composition, while their different physical forms would be
neglected.
If we say that, as values, commodities are mere congelations of human labour,
we reduce them by our analysis, it is true, to the abstraction, value; but we
ascribe to this value no form apart from their bodily form. It is otherwise in
the value-relation of one commodity to another. Here, the one stands forth in
its character of value by reason of its relation to the other.
By making the coat the equivalent of the linen, we equate the labour embodied
in the former to that in the latter. Now, it is true that the tailoring, which
makes the coat, is concrete labour of a different sort from the weaving which
makes the linen. But the act of equating it to the weaving, reduces the
tailoring to that which is really equal in the two kinds of labour, to their
common character of human labour. In this roundabout way, then, the fact is
expressed, that weaving also, in so far as it weaves value, has nothing to
distinguish it from tailoring, and, consequently, is abstract human labour. It
is the expression of equivalence between different sorts of commodities that
alone brings into relief the specific character of value-creating labour, and
this it does by actually reducing the different varieties of labour embodied in
the different kinds of commodities to their common quality of human labour in
the abstract. [18]
There is, however, something else required beyond the expression of the
specific character of the labour of which the value of the linen consists. Human
labour-power in motion, or human labour, creates value, but is not itself value.
It becomes value only in its congealed state, when embodied in the form of some
object. In order to express the value of the linen as a congelation of human
labour, that value must be expressed as having objective existence, as being a
something materially different from the linen itself, and yet a something common
to the linen and all other commodities. The problem is already solved.
When occupying the position of equivalent in the equation of value, the coat
ranks qualitatively as the equal of the linen, as something of the same kind,
because it is value. In this position it is a thing in which we see nothing but
value, or whose palpable bodily form represents value. Yet the coat itself, the
body of the commodity, coat, is a mere use-value. A coat as such no more tells
us it is value, than does the first piece of linen we take hold of. This shows
that when placed in value-relation to the linen, the coat signifies more than
when out of that relation, just as many a man strutting about in a gorgeous
uniform counts for more than when in mufti.
In the production of the coat, human labour-power, in the shape of tailoring,
must have been actually expended. Human labour is therefore accumulated in it.
In this aspect the coat is a depository of value, but though worn to a thread,
it does not let this fact show through. And as equivalent of the linen in the
value equation, it exists under this aspect alone, counts therefore as embodied
value, as a body that is value. A, for instance, cannot be "your majesty" to B,
unless at the same time majesty in B's eyes assumes the bodily form of A, and,
what is more, with every new father of the people, changes its features, hair,
and many other things besides.
Hence, in the value equation, in which the coat is the equivalent of the
linen, the coat officiates as the form of value. The value of the commodity
linen is expressed by the bodily form of the commodity coat, the value of one by
the use-value of the other. As a use-value, the linen is something palpably
different from the coat; as value, it is the same as the coat, and now has the
appearance of a coat. Thus the linen acquires a value-form different from its
physical form. The fact that it is value, is made manifest by its equality with
the coat, just as the sheep's nature of a Christian is shown in his resemblance
to the Lamb of God.
We see, then, all that our analysis of the value of commodities has already
told us, is told us by the linen itself, so soon as it comes into communication
with another commodity, the coat. Only it betrays its thoughts in that language
with which alone it is familiar, the language of commodities. In order to tell
us that its own value is created by labour in its abstract character of human
labour, it says that the coat, in so far as it is worth as much as the linen,
and therefore is value, consists of the same labour as the linen. In order to
inform us that its sublime reality as value is not the same as its buckram body,
it says that value has the appearance of a coat, and consequently that so far as
the linen is value, it and the coat are as like as two peas. We may here remark,
that the language of commodities has, besides Hebrew, many other more or less
correct dialects. The German "Wertsein," to be worth, for instance, expresses in
a less striking manner than the Romance verbs "valere," "valer," "valoir," that
the equating of commodity B to commodity A, is commodity A's own mode of
expressing its value. Paris vaut bien une messe.
By means, therefore, of the value-relation expressed in our equation, the
bodily form of commodity B becomes the value-form of commodity A, or the body of
commodity B acts as a mirror to the value of commodity A. [19]
By putting itself in relation with commodity B, as value in propria
personā, as the matter of which human labour is made up, the commodity A
converts the value in use, B, into the substance in which to express its, A's,
own value. The value of A, thus expressed in the use-value of B, has taken the
form of relative value.
The equation, 20 yards of linen = 1 coat, or 20 yards of linen are worth one
coat, implies that the same quantity of value-substance (congealed labour) is
embodied in both; that the two commodities have each cost the same amount of
labour of the same quantity of labour-time. But the labour-time necessary for
the production of 20 yards of linen or 1 coat varies with every change in the
productiveness of weaving or tailoring. We have now to consider the influence of
such changes on the quantitative aspect of the relative expression of value.
I. Let the value of the linen vary, [20]
that of the coat remaining constant. If, say in consequence of the exhaustion of
flax-growing soil, the labour-time necessary for the production of the linen be
doubled, the value of the linen will also be doubled. Instead of the equation,
20 yards of linen = 1 coat, we should have 20 yards of linen = 2 coats, since 1
coat would now contain only half the labour-time embodied in 20 yards of linen.
If, on the other hand, in consequence, say, of improved looms, this labour-time
be reduced by one-half, the value of the linen would fall by one-half.
Consequently, we should have 20 yards of linen = 1/2 coat. The relative value of
commodity A, i.e., its value expressed in commodity B, rises and falls
directly as the value of A, the value of B being supposed constant.
II. Let the value of the linen remain constant, while the value of the
coat varies. If, under these circumstances, in consequence, for instance, of a
poor crop of wool, the labour-time necessary for the production of a coat
becomes doubled, we have instead of 20 yards of linen = 1 coat, 20 yards of
linen = 1/2 coat. If, on the other hand, the value of the coat sinks by
one-half, then 20 yards of linen = 2 coats. Hence, if the value of commodity A
remain constant, its relative value expressed in commodity B rises and falls
inversely as the value of B.
If we compare the different cases in I. and II., we see that the same change
of magnitude in relative value may arise from totally opposite causes. Thus, the
equation, 20 yards of linen = 1 coat, becomes 20 yards of linen = 2 coats,
either, because the value of the linen has doubled, or because the value of the
coat has fallen by one-half; and it becomes 20 yards of linen = 1/2 coat,
either, because the value of the linen has fallen by one-half, or because the
value of the coat has doubled.
III. Let the quantities of labour-time respectively necessary for the
production of the linen and the coat vary simultaneously in the same direction
and in the same proportion. In this case 20 yards of linen continue equal to 1
coat, however much their values may have altered. Their change of value is seen
as soon as they are compared with a third commodity, whose value has remained
constant. If the values of all commodities rose or fell simultaneously, and in
the same proportion, their relative values would remain unaltered. Their real
change of value would appear from the diminished or increased quantity of
commodities produced in a given time.
IV. The labour-time respectively necessary for the production of the
linen and the coat, and therefore the value of these commodities may
simultaneously vary in the same direction, but at unequal rates or in opposite
directions, or in other ways. The effect of all these possible different
variations, on the relative value of a commodity, may be deduced from the
results of I., II., and III.
Thus real changes in the magnitude of value are neither unequivocally nor
exhaustively reflected in their relative expression, that is, in the equation
expressing the magnitude of relative value. The relative value of a commodity
may vary, although its value remains constant. Its relative value may remain
constant, although its value varies; and finally, simultaneous variations in the
magnitude of value and in that of its relative expression by no means
necessarily correspond in amount. [21]
When one commodity, such as a coat, serves as the equivalent of another, such
as linen, and coats consequently acquire the characteristic property of being
directly exchangeable with linen, we are far from knowing in what proportion the
two are exchangeable. The value of the linen being given in magnitude, that
proportion depends on the value of the coat. Whether the coat serves as the
equivalent and the linen as relative value, or the linen as the equivalent and
the coat as relative value, the magnitude of the coat's value is determined,
independently of its value-form, by the labour-time necessary for its
production. But whenever the coat assumes in the equation of value, the position
of equivalent, its value acquires no quantitative expression; on the contrary,
the commodity coat now figures only as a definite quantity of some article.
For instance, 40 yards of linen are worth -- what? 2 coats. Because the
commodity coat here plays the part of equivalent, because the use-value coat, as
opposed to the linen, figures as an embodiment of value, therefore a definite
number of coats suffices to express the definite quantity of value in the linen.
Two coats may therefore express the quantity of value of 40 yards of linen, but
they can never express the quantity of their own value. A superficial
observation of this fact, namely, that in the equation of value, the equivalent
figures exclusively as a simple quantity of some article, of some use-value, has
misled Bailey, as also many others, both before and after him, into seeing, in
the expression of value, merely a quantitative relation. The truth being, that
when a commodity acts as equivalent, no quantitative determination of its value
is expressed.
The first peculiarity that strikes us, in considering the form of the
equivalent, is this: use-value becomes the form of manifestation, the phenomenal
form of its opposite, value.
The bodily form of the commodity becomes its value-form. But, mark well, that
this quid pro quo exists in the case of any commodity B, only when some other
commodity A enters into a value-relation with it, and then only within the
limits of this relation. Since no commodity can stand in the relation of
equivalent to itself, and thus turn its own bodily shape into the expression of
its own value, every commodity is compelled to choose some other commodity for
its equivalent, and to accept the use-value, that is to say, the bodily shape of
that other commodity as the form of its own value.
One of the measures that we apply to commodities as material substances, as
use-values, will serve to illustrate this point. A sugar-loaf being a body, is
heavy, and therefore has weight: but we can neither see nor touch this weight.
We then take various pieces of iron, whose weight has been determined
beforehand. The iron, as iron, is no more the form of manifestation of weight,
than is the sugar-loaf. Nevertheless, in order to express the sugar-loaf as so
much weight, we put it into a weight-relation with the iron. In this relation,
the iron officiates as a body representing nothing but weight. A certain
quantity of iron therefore serves as the measure of the weight of the sugar, and
represents, in relation to the sugar-loaf, weight embodied, the form of
manifestation of weight. This part is played by the iron only within this
relation, into which the sugar or any other body, whose weight has to be
determined, enters with the iron. Were they not both heavy, they could not enter
into this relation, and the one could therefore not serve as the expression of
the weight of the other. When we throw both into the scales, we see in reality,
that as weight they are both the same, and that, therefore, when taken in proper
proportions, they have the same weight. Just as the substance iron, as a measure
of weight, represents in relation to the sugar-loaf weight alone, so, in our
expression of value, the material object, coat, in relation to the linen,
represents value alone.
Here, however, the analogy ceases. The iron, in the expression of the weight
of the sugar-loaf, represents a natural property common to both bodies, namely
their weight; but the coat, in the expression of value of the linen, represents
a non-natural property of both, something purely social, namely, their value.
Since the relative form of value of a commodity -- the linen, for example --
expresses the value of that commodity, as being something wholly different from
its substance and properties, as being, for instance, coat-like, we see that
this expression itself indicates that some social relation lies at the bottom of
it. With the equivalent form it is just the contrary. The very essence of this
form is that the material commodity itself -- the coat -- just as it is,
expresses value, and is endowed with the form of value by Nature itself. Of
course this holds good only so long as the value-relation exists, in which the
coat stands in the position of equivalent to the linen. [22]
Since, however, the properties of a thing are not the result of its relations to
other things, but only manifest themselves in such relations, the coat seems to
be endowed with its equivalent form, its property of being directly
exchangeable, just as much by Nature as it is endowed with the property of being
heavy, or the capacity to keep us warm. Hence the enigmatical character of the
equivalent form which escapes the notice of the bourgeois political economist,
until this form, completely developed, confronts him in the shape of money. He
then seeks to explain away the mystical character of gold and silver, by
substituting for them less dazzling commodities, and by reciting, with ever
renewed satisfaction, the catalogue of all possible commodities which at one
time or another have played the part of equivalent. He has not the least
suspicion that the most simple expression of value, such as 20 yds. of linen = 1
coat, already propounds the riddle of the equivalent form for our solution.
The body of the commodity that serves as the equivalent, figures as the
materialisation of human labour in the abstract, and is at the same time the
product of some specifically useful concrete labour. This concrete labour
becomes, therefore, the medium for expressing abstract human labour. If on the
one hand the coat ranks as nothing but the embodiment of abstract human labour,
so, on the other hand, the tailoring which is actually embodied in it, counts as
nothing but the form under which that abstract labour is realised. In the
expression of value of the linen, the utility of the tailoring consists, not in
making clothes, but in making an object, which we at once recognise to be Value,
and therefore to be a congelation of labour, but of labour indistinguishable
from that realised in the value of the linen. In order to act as such a mirror
of value, the labour of tailoring must reflect nothing besides its own abstract
quality of being human labour generally.
In tailoring, as well as in weaving, human labour-power is expended. Both,
therefore, possess the general property of being human labour, and may,
therefore, in certain cases, such as in the production of value, have to be
considered under this aspect alone. There is nothing mysterious in this. But in
the expression of value there is a complete turn of the tables. For instance,
how is the fact to be expressed that weaving creates the value of the linen, not
by virtue of being weaving, as such, but by reason of its general property of
being human labour? Simply by opposing to weaving that other particular form of
concrete labour (in this instance tailoring), which produces the equivalent of
the product of weaving. Just as the coat in its bodily form became a direct
expression of value, so now does tailoring, a concrete form of labour, appear as
the direct and palpable embodiment of human labour generally.
Hence, the second peculiarity of the equivalent form is, that concrete labour
becomes the form under which its opposite, abstract human labour, manifests
itself.
But because this concrete labour, tailoring in our case, ranks as, and is
directly identified with, undifferentiated human labour, it also ranks as
identical with any other sort of labour, and therefore with that embodied in the
linen. Consequently, although, like all other commodity producing labour, it is
the labour of private individuals, yet, at the same time, it ranks as labour
directly social in its character. This is the reason why it results in a product
directly exchangeable with other commodities. We have then a third peculiarity
of the equivalent form, namely, that the labour of private individuals takes the
form of its opposite, labour directly social in its form.
The two latter peculiarities of the equivalent form will become more
intelligible if we go back to the great thinker who was the first to analyse so
many forms, whether of thought, society, or Nature, and amongst them also the
form of value. I mean Aristotle.
In the first place, he clearly enunciates that the money-form of commodities
is only the further development of the simple form of value- i.e., of the
expression of the value of one commodity in some other commodity taken at
random; for he says --
Aristotle therefore, himself, tells us, what barred the way to his further
analysis; it was the absence of any concept of value. What is that equal
something, that common substance, which admits of the value of the beds being
expressed by a house? Such a thing, in truth, cannot exist, says Aristotle. And
why not? Compared with the beds, the house does represent something equal to
them, in so far as it represents what is really equal, both in the beds and the
house. And that is -- human labour.
There was, however, an important fact which prevented Aristotle from seeing
that, to attribute value to commodities, is merely a mode of expressing all
labour as equal human labour, and consequently as labour of equal quality. Greek
society was founded upon slavery, and had, therefore, for its natural basis, the
inequality of men and of their labour-powers. The secret of the expression of
value, namely, that all kinds of labour are equal and equivalent, because, and
so far as they are human labour in general, cannot be deciphered, until the
notion of human equality has already acquired the fixity of a popular prejudice.
This, however, is possible only in a society in which the great mass of the
produce of labour takes the form of commodities, in which, consequently, the
dominant relation between man and man, is that of owners of commodities. The
brilliancy of Aristotle's genius is shown by this alone, that he discovered, in
the expression of the value of commodities, a relation of equality. The peculiar
conditions of the society in which he lived, alone prevented him from
discovering what, "in truth," was at the bottom of this equality.
Our analysis has shown, that the form or expression of the value of a
commodity originates in the nature of value, and not that value and its
magnitude originate in the mode of their expression as exchange-value. This,
however, is the delusion as well of the mercantilists and their recent revivers,
Ferrier, Ganilh, [23]
and others, as also of their antipodes, the modern bagmen of Free-trade, such as
Bastiat. The mercantilists lay special stress on the qualitative aspect of the
expression of value, and consequently on the equivalent form of commodities,
which attains its full perfection in money. The modern hawkers of Free-trade,
who must get rid of their article at any price, on the other hand, lay most
stress on the quantitative aspect of the relative form of value. For them there
consequently exists neither value, nor magnitude of value, anywhere except in
its expression by means of the exchange relation of commodities, that is, in the
daily list of prices current. Macleod, who has taken upon himself to dress up
the confused ideas of Lombard Street in the most learned finery, is a successful
cross between the superstitious mercantilists, and the enlightened Free-trade
bagmen.
A close scrutiny of the expression of the value of A in terms of B, contained
in the equation expressing the value-relation of A to B, has shown us that,
within that relation, the bodily form of A figures only as a use-value, the
bodily form of B only as the form or aspect of value. The opposition or contrast
existing internally in each commodity between use-value and value, is,
therefore, made evident externally by two commodities being placed in such
relation to each other, that the commodity whose value it is sought to express,
figures directly as a mere use-value, while the commodity in which that value is
to be expressed, figures directly as mere exchange-value. Hence the elementary
form of value of a commodity is the elementary form in which the contrast
contained in that commodity, between use-value and value, becomes apparent.
Every product of labour is, in all states of society, a use-value; but it is
only at a definite historical epoch in a society's development that such a
product becomes a commodity, viz., at the epoch when the labour spent on the
production of a useful article becomes expressed as one of the objective
qualities of that article, i.e., as its value. It therefore follows that
the elementary value-form is also the primitive form under which a product of
labour appears historically as a commodity, and that the gradual transformation
of such products into commodities, proceeds pari passu with the development of
the value-form.
We perceive, at first sight, the deficiencies of the elementary form of
value: it is a mere germ, which must undergo a series of metamorphoses before it
can ripen into the price-form.
The expression of the value of commodity A in terms of any other commodity B,
merely distinguishes the value from the use-value of A, and therefore places A
merely in a relation of exchange with a single different commodity, B; but it is
still far from expressing A's qualitative equality, and quantitative
proportionality, to all commodities. To the elementary relative value-form of a
commodity, there corresponds the single equivalent form of one other commodity.
Thus, in the relative expression of value of the linen, the coat assumes the
form of equivalent, or of being directly exchangeable, only in relation to a
single commodity, the linen.
Nevertheless, the elementary form of value passes by an easy transition into
a more complete form. It is true that by means of the elementary form, the value
of a commodity A, becomes expressed in terms of one, and only one, other
commodity. But that one may be a commodity of any kind, coat, iron, corn, or
anything else. Therefore, according as A is placed in relation with one or the
other, we get for one and the same commodity, different elementary expressions
of value. [24]
The number of such possible expressions is limited only by the number of the
different kinds of commodities distinct from it. The isolated expression of A's
value, is therefore convertible into a series, prolonged to any length, of the
different elementary expressions of that value.
In the first form, 20 yds. of linen = 1 coat, it might, for ought that
otherwise appears, be pure accident, that these two commodities are exchangeable
in definite quantities. In the second form, on the contrary, we perceive at once
the background that determines, and is essentially different from, this
accidental appearance. The value of the linen remains unaltered in magnitude,
whether expressed in coats, coffee, or iron, or in numberless different
commodities, the property of as many different owners. The accidental relation
between two individual commodity-owners disappears. It becomes plain, that it is
not the exchange of commodities which regulates the magnitude of their value;
but, on the contrary, that it is the magnitude of their value which controls
their exchange proportions.
The expanded relative value-form is, however, nothing but the sum of the
elementary relative expressions or equations of the first kind, such as
The forms A and B were fit only to express the value of a commodity as
something distinct from its use-value or material form.
The first- form, A, furnishes such equations as the following: -- 1 coat = 20
yards of linen, 10 lbs. of tea = 1/2 a ton of iron. The value of the coat is
equated to linen, that of the tea to iron. But to be equated to linen, and again
to iron, is to be as different as are linen and iron. This forms it is plain,
occurs practically only in the first beginning, when the products of labour are
converted into commodities by accidental and occasional exchanges.
The second form, B, distinguishes, in a more adequate manner than the first,
the value of a commodity from its use-value, for the value of the coat is there
placed in contrast under all possible shapes with the bodily form of the coat;
it is equated to linen, to iron, to tea, in short, to everything else, only not
to itself, the coat. On the other hand, any general expression of value common
to all is directly excluded; for, in the equation of value of each commodity,
all other commodities now appear only under the form of equivalents. The
expanded form of value comes into actual existence for the first time so soon as
a particular product of labour, such as cattle, is no longer exceptionally, but
habitually, exchanged for various other commodities.
The third and lastly developed form expresses the values of the whole world
of commodities in terms of a single commodity set apart for the purpose, namely,
the linen, and thus represents to us their values by means of their equality
with linen. The value of every commodity is now, by being equated to linen, not
only differentiated from its own use-value, but from all other use-values
generally, and is, by that very fact, expressed as that which is common to all
commodities. By this form, commodities are, for the first time, effectively
brought into relation with one another as values, or made to appear as
exchange-values.
The two earlier forms either express the value of each commodity in terms of
a single commodity of a different kind, or in a series of many such commodities.
In both cases, it is, so to say, the special business of each single commodity
to find an expression for its value, and this it does without the help of the
others. These others, with respect to the former, play the passive parts of
equivalents. The general form of value, C, results from the joint action of the
whole world of commodities, and from that alone. A commodity can acquire a
general expression of its value only by all other commodities, simultaneously
with it, expressing their values in the same equivalent; and every new commodity
must follow suit. It thus becomes evident that since the existence of
commodities as values is purely social, this social existence can be expressed
by the totality of their social relations alone, and consequently that the form
of their value must be a socially recognised form.
All commodities being equated to linen now appear not only as qualitatively
equal as values generally, but also as values whose magnitudes are capable of
comparison. By expressing the magnitudes of their values in one and the same
material, the linen, those magnitudes are also compared with each other For
instance, 10 Ibs. of tea = 20 yards of linen, and 40 lbs. of coffee = 20 yards
of linen. Therefore, 10 Ibs of tea = 40 Ibs. of coffee. In other words, there is
contained in 1 lb. of coffee only one-fourth as much substance of value --
labour -- as is contained in 1 lb. of tea.
The general form of relative value, embracing the whole world of commodities,
converts the single commodity that is excluded from the rest, and made to play
the part of equivalent -- here the linen -- into the universal equivalent. The
bodily form of the linen is now the form assumed in common by the values of all
commodities; it therefore becomes directly exchangeable with all and every of
them. The substance linen becomes the visible incarnation, the social chrysalis
state of every kind of human labour. Weaving, which is the labour of certain
private individuals producing a particular article, linen, acquires in
consequence a social character, the character of equality with all other kinds
of labour. The innumerable equations of which the general form of value is
composed, equate in turn the labour embodied in the linen to that embodied in
every other commodity, and they thus convert weaving into the general form of
manifestation of undifferentiated human labour. In this manner the labour
realised in the values of commodities is presented not only under its negative
aspect, under which abstraction is made from every concrete form and useful
property of actual work, but its own positive nature is made to reveal itself
expressly. The general value-form is the reduction of all kinds of actual labour
to their common character of being human labour generally, of being the
expenditure of human labour-power.
The general value-form, which represents all products of labour as mere
congelations of undifferentiated human labour, shows by its very structure that
it is the social resume of the world of commodities. That form consequently
makes it indisputably evident that in the world of commodities the character
possessed by all labour of being human labour constitutes its specific social
character.
The primary or isolated relative form of value of one commodity converts some
other commodity into an isolated equivalent. The expanded form of relative
value, which is the expression of the value of one commodity in terms of all
other commodities, endows those other commodities with the character of
particular equivalents differing in kind. And lastly, a particular kind of
commodity acquires the character of universal equivalent, because all other
commodities make it the material in which they uniformly express their value.
The antagonism between the relative form of value and the equivalent form,
the two poles of the value-form, is developed concurrently with that form
itself.
The first form, 20 yds. of linen = one coat, already contains this
antagonism, without as yet fixing it. According as we read this equation
forwards or backwards, the parts played by the linen and the coat are different.
In the one case the relative value of the linen is expressed in the coat, in the
other case the relative value of the coat is expressed in the linen. In this
first form of value, therefore, it is difficult to grasp the polar contrast.
Form B shows that only one single commodity at a time can completely expand
its relative value, and that it acquires this expanded form only because, and in
so far as, all other commodities are, with respect to it, equivalents. Here we
cannot reverse the equation, as we can the equation 20 yds. of linen = 1 coat,
without altering its general character, and converting it from the expanded form
of value into the general form of value.
Finally, the form C gives to the world of commodities a general social
relative form of value, because, and in so far as, thereby all commodities, with
the exception of one, are excluded from the equivalent form. A single commodity,
the linen, appears therefore to have acquired the character of direct
exchangeability with every other commodity because, and in so far as, this
character is denied to every other commodity. [26]
The commodity that figures as universal equivalent, is, on the other hand,
excluded from the relative value-form. If the linen, or any other commodity
serving as universal equivalent, were, at the same time, to share in the
relative form of value, it would have to serve as its own equivalent. We should
then have 20 yds. of linen = 20 yds. of linen; this tautology expresses neither
value, nor magnitude of value. In order to express the relative value of the
universal equivalent, we must rather reverse the form C. This equivalent has no
relative form of value in common with other commodities, but its value is
relatively expressed by a never ending series of other commodities.
Thus, the expanded form of relative value, or form B, now shows itself as the
specific form of relative value for the equivalent commodity.
The particular commodity, with whose bodily form the equivalent form is thus
socially identified, now becomes the money-commodity, or serves as money. It
becomes the special social function of that commodity, and consequently its
social monopoly, to play within the world of commodities the part of the
universal equivalent. Amongst the commodities which, in form B, figure as
particular equivalents of the linen, and, in form C, express in common their
relative values in linen, this foremost place has been attained by one in
particular- namely, gold. If, then, in form C we replace the linen by gold, we
get,
Gold is now money with reference to all other commodities only because it was
previously, with reference to them, a simple commodity. Like all other
commodities, it was also capable of serving as an equivalent, either as simple
equivalent in isolated exchanges, or as particular equivalent by the side of
others. Gradually it began to serve, within varying limits, as universal
equivalent. So soon as it monopolises this position in the expression of value
for the world of commodities, it becomes the money commodity, and then, and not
till then, does form D become distinct from form C, and the general form of
value become changed into the money-form.
The elementary expression of the relative value of a single commodity, such
as linen, in terms of the commodity, such as gold, that plays the part of money,
is the price-form of that commodity. The price-form of the linen is therefore
A commodity appears, at first sight, a very trivial
thing, and easily understood. Its analysis shows that it is, in reality, a very
queer thing, abounding in metaphysical subtleties and theological niceties. So
far as it is a value in use, there is nothing mysterious about it, whether we
consider it from the point of view that by its properties it is capable of
satisfying human wants, or from the point that those properties are the product
of human labour. It is as clear as noon-day, that man, by his industry, changes
the forms of the materials furnished by Nature, in such a way as to make them
useful to him. The form of wood, for instance, is altered, by making a table out
of it. Yet, for all that, the table continues to be that common, every-day
thing, wood. But, so soon as it steps forth as a commodity, it is changed into
something transcendent. It not only stands with its feet on the ground, but, in
relation to all other commodities, it stands on its head, and evolves out of its
wooden brain grotesque ideas, far more wonderful than "table-turning" ever was.
The mystical character of commodities does not originate, therefore, in their
use-value. Just as little does it proceed from the nature of the determining
factors of value. For, in the first place, however varied the useful kinds of
labour, or productive activities, may be, it is a physiological fact, that they
are functions of the human organism, and that each such function, whatever may
be its nature or form, is essentially the expenditure of human brain, nerves,
muscles, &c. Secondly, with regard to that which forms the ground-work for
the quantitative determination of value, namely, the duration of that
expenditure, or the quantity of labour, it is quite clear that there is a
palpable difference between its quantity and quality. In all states of society,
the labour-time that it costs to produce the means of subsistence, must
necessarily be an object of interest to mankind, though not of equal interest in
different stages of development. [27]
And lastly, from the moment that men in any way work for one another, their
labour assumes a social form.
Whence, then, arises the enigmatical character of the product of labour, so
soon as it assumes the form of commodities? Clearly from this form itself. The
equality of all sorts of human labour is expressed objectively by their products
all being equally values; the measure of the expenditure of labour-power by the
duration of that expenditure, takes the form of the quantity of value of the
products of labour; and finally the mutual relations of the producers, within
which the social character of their labour affirms itself, take the form of a
social relation between the products.
A commodity is therefore a mysterious thing, simply because in it the social
character of men's labour appears to them as an objective character stamped upon
the product of that labour; because the relation of the producers to the sum
total of their own labour is presented to them as a social relation, existing
not between themselves, but between the products of their labour. This is the
reason why the products of labour become commodities, social things whose
qualities are at the same time perceptible and imperceptible by the senses. In
the same way the light from an object is perceived by us not as the subjective
excitation of our optic nerve, but as the objective form of something outside
the eye itself. But, in the act of seeing, there is at all events, an actual
passage of light from one thing to another, from the external object to the eye.
There is a physical relation between physical things. But it is different with
commodities. There, the existence of the things qua commodities, and the
value-relation between the products of labour which stamps them as commodities,
have absolutely no connexion with their physical properties and with the
material relations arising therefrom. There it is a definite social relation
between men, that assumes, in their eyes, the fantastic form of a relation
between things. In order, therefore, to find an analogy, we must have recourse
to the mist-enveloped regions of the religious world. In that world the
productions of the human brain appear as independent beings endowed with life,
and entering into relation both with one another and the human race. So it is in
the world of commodities with the products of men's hands. This I call the
Fetishism which attaches itself to the products of labour, so soon as they are
produced as commodities, and which is therefore inseparable from the production
of commodities.
This Fetishism of commodities has its origin, as the foregoing analysis has
already shown, in the peculiar social character of the labour that produces
them.
As a general rule, articles of utility become commodities, only because they
are products of the labour of private individuals or groups of individuals who
carry on their work independently of each other. The sum total of the labour of
all these private individuals forms the aggregate labour of society. Since the
producers do not come into social contact with each other until they exchange
their products, the specific social character of each producer's labour does not
show itself except in the act of exchange. In other words, the labour of the
individual asserts itself as a part of the labour of society, only by means of
the relations which the act of exchange establishes directly between the
products, and indirectly, through them, between the producers. To the latter,
therefore, the relations connecting the labour of one individual with that of
the rest appear, not as direct social relations between individuals at work, but
as what they really are, material relations between persons and social relations
between things. It is only by being exchanged that the products of labour
acquire, as values, one uniform social status, distinct from their varied forms
of existence as objects of utility. This division of a product into a useful
thing and a value becomes practically important, only when exchange has acquired
such an extension that useful articles are produced for the purpose of being
exchanged, and their character as values has therefore to be taken into account,
beforehand, during production. From this moment the labour of the individual
producer acquires socially a two-fold character. On the one hand, it must, as a
definite useful kind of labour, satisfy a definite social want, and thus hold
its place as part and parcel of the collective labour of all, as a branch of a
social division of labour that has sprung up spontaneously. On the other hand,
it can satisfy the manifold wants of the individual producer himself, only in so
far as the mutual exchangeability of all kinds of useful private labour is an
established social fact, and therefore the private useful labour of each
producer ranks on an equality with that of all others. The equalisation of the
most different kinds of labour can be the result only of an abstraction from
their inequalities, or of reducing them to their common denominator, viz.
expenditure of human labour-power or human labour in the abstract. The two-fold
social character of the labour of the individual appears to him, when reflected
in his brain, only under those forms which are impressed upon that labour in
every-day practice by the exchange of products. In this way, the character that
his own labour possesses of being socially useful takes the form of the
condition, that the product must be not only useful, but useful for others, and
the social character that his particular labour has of being the equal of all
other particular kinds of labour, takes the form that all the physically
different articles that are the products of labour. have one common quality,
viz., that of having value.
Hence, when we bring the products of our labour into relation with each other
as values, it is not because we see in these articles the material receptacles
of homogeneous human labour. Quite the contrary: whenever, by an exchange, we
equate as values our different products, by that very act, we also equate, as
human labour, the different kinds of labour expended upon them. We are not aware
of this, nevertheless we do it. [28]
Value, therefore, does not stalk about with a label describing what it is. It is
value, rather, that converts every product into a social hieroglyphic. Later on,
we try to decipher the hieroglyphic, to get behind the secret of our own social
products; for to stamp an object of utility as a value, is just as much a social
product as language. The recent scientific discovery, that the products of
labour, so far as they are values, are but material expressions of the human
labour spent in their production, marks, indeed, an epoch in the history of the
development of the human race, but, by no means, dissipates the mist through
which the social character of labour appears to us to be an objective character
of the products themselves. The fact, that in the particular form of production
with which we are dealing, viz., the production of commodities, the specific
social character of private labour carried on independently, consists in the
equality of every kind of that labour, by virtue of its being human labour,
which character, therefore, assumes in the product the form of value -- this
fact appears to the producers, notwithstanding the discovery above referred to,
to be just as real and final, as the fact, that, after the discovery by science
of the component gases of air, the atmosphere itself remained unaltered.
What, first of all, practically concerns producers when they make an
exchange, is the question, how much of some other product they get for their
own? in what proportions the products are exchangeable? When these proportions
have, by custom, attained a certain stability, they appear to result from the
nature of the products, so that, for instance, one ton of iron and two ounces of
gold appear as naturally to be of equal value as a pound of gold and a pound of
iron in spite of their different physical and chemical qualities appear to be of
equal weight. The character of having value, when once impressed upon products,
obtains fixity only by reason of their acting and re-acting upon each other as
quantities of value. These quantities vary continually, independently of the
will, foresight and action of the producers. To them, their own social action
takes the form of the action of objects, which rule the producers instead of
being ruled by them. It requires a fully developed production of commodities
before, from accumulated experience alone, the scientific conviction springs up,
that all the different kinds of private labour, which are carried on
independently of each other, and yet as spontaneously developed branches of the
social division of labour, are continually being reduced to the quantitative
proportions in which society requires them. And why? Because, in the midst of
all the accidental and ever fluctuating exchange-relations between the products,
the labour-time socially necessary for their production forcibly asserts itself
like an over-riding law of Nature. The law of gravity thus asserts itself when a
house falls about our ears. [29]
The determination of the magnitude of value by labour-time is therefore a
secret, hidden under the apparent fluctuations in the relative values of
commodities. Its discovery, while removing all appearance of mere accidentality
from the determination of the magnitude of the values of products, yet in no way
alters the mode in which that determination takes place.
Man's reflections on the forms of social life, and consequently, also, his
scientific analysis of those forms, take a course directly opposite to that of
their actual historical development. He begins, post festum, with the results of
the process of development ready to hand before him. The characters that stamp
products as commodities, and whose establishment is a necessary preliminary to
the circulation of commodities, have already acquired the stability of natural,
self-understood forms of social life, before man seeks to decipher, not their
historical character, for in his eyes they are immutable, but their meaning.
Consequently it was the analysis of the prices of commodities that alone led to
the determination of the magnitude of value, and it was the common expression of
all commodities in money that alone led to the establishment of their characters
as values. It is, however, just this ultimate money-form of the world of
commodities that actually conceals, instead of disclosing, the social character
of private labour, and the social relations between the individual producers.
When I state that coats or boots stand in a relation to linen, because it is the
universal incarnation of abstract human labour, the absurdity of the statement
is self-evident. Nevertheless, when the producers of coats and boots compare
those articles with linen, or, what is the same thing, with gold or silver, as
the universal equivalent, they express the relation between their own private
labour and the collective labour of society in the same absurd form.
The categories of bourgeois economy consist of such like forms. They are
forms of thought expressing with social validity the conditions and relations of
a definite, historically determined mode of production, viz., the production of
commodities. The whole mystery of commodities, all the magic and necromancy that
surrounds the products of labour as long as they take the form of commodities,
vanishes therefore, so soon as we come to other forms of production.
Since Robinson Crusoe's experiences are a favourite theme with political
economists, [30]
let us take a look at him on his island. Moderate though he be, yet some few
wants he has to satisfy, and must therefore do a little useful work of various
sorts, such as making tools and furniture, taming goats, fishing and hunting. Of
his prayers and the like we take no account, since they are a source of pleasure
to him, and he looks upon them as so much recreation. In spite of the variety of
his work, he knows that his labour, whatever its form, is but the activity of
one and the same Robinson, and consequently, that it consists of nothing but
different modes of human labour. Necessity itself compels him to apportion his
time accurately between his different kinds of work. Whether one kind occupies a
greater space in his general activity than another, depends on the difficulties,
greater or less as the case may be, to be overcome in attaining the useful
effect aimed at. This our friend Robinson soon learns by experience, and having
rescued a watch, ledger, and pen and ink from the wreck, commences, like a
true-born Briton, to keep a set of books. His stock-book contains a list of the
objects of utility that belong to him, of the operations necessary for their
production; and lastly, of the labour-time that definite quantities of those
objects have, on an average, cost him. All the relations between Robinson and
the objects that form this wealth of his own creation, are here so simple and
clear as to be intelligible without exertion, even to Mr. Sedley Taylor. And yet
those relations contain all that is essential to the determination of value.
Let us now transport ourselves from Robinson's island bathed in light to the
European middle ages shrouded in darkness. Here, instead of the independent man,
we find everyone dependent, serfs and lords, vassals and suzerains, laymen and
clergy. Personal dependence here characterises the social relations of
production just as much as it does the other spheres of life organised on the
basis of that production. But for the very reason that personal dependence forms
the ground-work of society, there is no necessity for labour and its products to
assume a fantastic form different from their reality. They take the shape, in
the transactions of society, of services in kind and payments in kind. Here the
particular and natural form of labour, and not, as in a society based on
production of commodities, its general abstract form is the immediate social
form of labour. Compulsory labour is just as properly measured by time, as
commodity-producing labour; but every serf knows that what he expends in the
service of his lord, is a definite quantity of his own personal labour-power.
The tithe to be rendered to the priest is more matter of fact than his blessing.
No matter, then, what we may think of the parts played by the different classes
of people themselves in this society, the social relations between individuals
in the performance of their labour, appear at all events as their own mutual
personal relations, and are not disguised under the shape of social relations
between the products of labour.
For an example of labour in common or directly associated labour, we have no
occasion to go back to that spontaneously developed form which we find on the
threshold of the history of all civilised races. [31]
We have one close at hand in the patriarchal industries of a peasant family,
that produces corn, cattle, yarn, linen, and clothing for home use. These
different articles are, as regards the family, so many products of its labour,
but as between themselves, they are not commodities. The different kinds of
labour, such as tillage, cattle tending, spinning, weaving and making clothes,
which result in the various products, are in themselves, and such as they are,
direct social functions, because functions of the family, which, just as much as
a society based on the production of commodities, possesses a spontaneously
developed system of division of labour. The distribution of the work within the
family, and the regulation of the labour-time of the several members, depend as
well upon differences of age and sex as upon natural conditions varying with the
seasons. The labour-power of each individual, by its very nature, operates in
this case merely as a definite portion of the whole labour-power of the family,
and therefore, the measure of the expenditure of individual labour-power by its
duration, appears here by its very nature as a social character of their labour.
Let us now picture to ourselves, by way of change, a community of free
individuals, carrying on their work with the means of production in common, in
which the labour-power of all the different individuals is consciously applied
as the combined labour-power of the community. All the characteristics of
Robinson's labour are here repeated, but with this difference, that they are
social, instead of individual. Everything produced by him was exclusively the
result of his own personal labour, and therefore simply an object of use for
himself. The total product of our community is a social product. One portion
serves as fresh means of production and remains social. But another portion is
consumed by the members as means of subsistence. A distribution of this portion
amongst them is consequently necessary. The mode of this distribution will vary
with the productive organisation of the community, and the degree of historical
development attained by the producers. We will assume, but merely for the sake
of a parallel with the production of commodities, that the share of each
individual producer in the means of subsistence is determined by his
labour-time. Labour-time would, in that case, play a double part. Its
apportionment in accordance with a definite social plan maintains the proper
proportion between the different kinds of work to be done and the various wants
of the community. On the other hand, it also serves as a measure of the portion
of the common labour borne by each individual, and of his share in the part of
the total product destined for individual consumption. The social relations of
the individual producers, with regard both to their labour and to its products,
are in this case perfectly simple and intelligible, and that with regard not
only to production but also to distribution.
The religious world is but the reflex of the real world. And for a society
based upon the production of commodities, in which the producers in general
enter into social relations with one another by treating their products as
commodities and values, whereby they reduce their individual private labour to
the standard of homogeneous human labour-for such a society, Christianity with
its cultus of abstract man, more especially in its bourgeois developments,
Protestantism, Deism, &c., is the most fitting form of religion. In the
ancient Asiatic and other ancient modes of production, we find that the
conversion of products into commodities, and therefore the conversion of men
into producers of commodities, holds a subordinate place, which, however,
increases in importance as the primitive communities approach nearer and nearer
to their dissolution. Trading nations, properly so called, exist in the ancient
world only in its interstices, like the gods of Epicurus in the Intermundia, or
like Jews in the pores of Polish society. Those ancient social organisms of
production are, as compared with bourgeois society, extremely simple and
transparent. But they are founded either on the immature development of man
individually, who has not yet severed the umbilical cord that unites him with
his fellowmen in a primitive tribal community, or upon direct relations of
subjection. They can arise and exist only when the development of the productive
power of labour has not risen beyond a low stage, and when, therefore, the
social relations within the sphere of material life, between man and man, and
between man and Nature, are correspondingly narrow. This narrowness is reflected
in the ancient worship of Nature, and in the other elements of the popular
religions. The religious reflex of the real world can, in any case, only then
finally vanish, when the practical relations of every-day life offer to man none
but perfectly intelligible and reasonable relations with regard to his fellowmen
and to Nature.
The life-process of society, which is based on the process of material
production, does not strip off its mystical veil until it is treated as
production by freely associated men, and is consciously regulated by them in
accordance with a settled plan. This, however, demands for society a certain
material ground-work or set of conditions of existence which in their turn are
the spontaneous product of a long and painful process of development.
Political Economy has indeed analysed, however incompletely, [32]
value and its magnitude, and has discovered what lies beneath these forms. But
it has never once asked the question why labour is represented by the value of
its product and labour-time by the magnitude of that value. [33]
These formulae, which bear it stamped upon them in unmistakable letters that
they belong to a state of society, in which the process of production has the
mastery over man, instead of being controlled by him, such formulae appear to
the bourgeois intellect to be as much a self-evident necessity imposed by Nature
as productive labour itself. Hence forms of social production that preceded the
bourgeois form, are treated by the bourgeoisie in much the same way as the
Fathers of the Church treated pre-Christian religions. [34]
To what extent some economists are misled by the Fetishism inherent in
commodities, or by the objective appearance of the social characteristics of
labour, is shown, amongst other ways, by the dull and tedious quarrel over the
part played by Nature in the formation of exchange-value. Since exchange-value
is a definite social manner of expressing the amount of labour bestowed upon an
object, Nature has no more to do with it, than it has in fixing the course of
exchange.
The mode of production in which the product takes the form of a commodity, or
is produced directly for exchange, is the most general and most embryonic form
of bourgeois production. It therefore makes its appearance at an early date in
history, though not in the same predominating and characteristic manner as
now-a-days. Hence its Fetish character is comparatively easy to be seen through.
But when we come to more concrete forms, even this appearance of simplicity
vanishes. Whence arose the illusions of the monetary system? To it gold and
silver, when serving as money, did not represent a social relation between
producers, but were natural objects with strange social properties. And modern
economy, which looks down with such disdain on the monetary system, does not its
superstition come out as clear as noon-day, whenever it treats of capital? How
long is it since economy discarded the physiocratic illusion, that rents grow
out of the soil and not out of society?
But not to anticipate, we will content ourselves with yet another example
relating to the commodity-form. Could commodities themselves speak, they would
say: Our use-value may be a thing that interests men. It is no part of us as
objects. What, however, does belong to us as objects, is our value. Our natural
intercourse as commodities proves it. In the eyes of each other we are nothing
but exchange-values. Now listen how those commodities speak through the mouth of
the economist. "Value" -- (i.e., exchange-value) "is a property of
things, riches" -- (i.e., use-value) "of man. Value, in this sense,
necessarily implies exchanges, riches do not." [35]
"Riches" (use-value) "are the attribute of men, value is the attribute of
commodities. A man or a community is rich, a pearl or a diamond is valuable... A
pearl or a diamond is valuable" as a pearl or a diamond. [36]
So far no chemist has ever discovered exchange-value either in a pearl or a
diamond. The economic discoverers of this chemical element, who by-the-by lay
special claim to critical acumen, find however that the use-value of objects
belongs to them independently of their material properties, while their value,
on the other hand, forms a part of them as objects. What confirms them in this
view, is the peculiar circumstance that the use-value of objects is realised
without exchange, by means of a direct relation between the objects and man,
while, on the other hand, their value is realised only by exchange, that is, by
means of a social process. Who fails here to call to mind our good friend,
Dogberry, who informs neighbour Seacoal, that, "To be a well-favoured man is the
gift of fortune; but reading and writing comes by Nature." [37]
[1] Karl Marx, "Zur Kritik der Politischen Oekonomie."
Berlin, 1859, p. 3.
[2] "Desire implies want, it is the appetite of the mind,
and as natural as hunger to the body.... The greatest number (of things) have
their value from supplying the wants of the mind." Nicholas Barbon: "A Discourse
Concerning Coining the New Money Lighter. In Answer to Mr. Locke's
Considerations," &c., London, 1696, pp. 2, 3.
[3] "Things have an intrinsick vertue" (this is Barbon's
special term for value in use) "which in all places have the same vertue; as the
loadstone to attract iron" (l.c., p. 6). The property which the magnet possesses
of attracting iron, became of use only after by means of that property the
polarity of the magnet had been discovered.
[4] "The natural worth of anything consists in its fitness
to supply the necessities, or serve the conveniencies of human life." (John
Locke, "Some Considerations on the Consequences of the Lowering of Interest,
1691," in Works Edit. Lond., 1777, Vol. II., p. 28.) In English writers of the
17th century we frequently find "worth" in the sense of value in use, and
"value" in the sense of exchange-value. This is quite in accordance with the
spirit of a language that likes to use a Teutonic word for the actual thing, and
a Romance word for its reflexion.
[5] In bourgeois societies the economic fictio juris
prevails, that every one, as a buyer, possesses an encyclopedic knowledge of
commodities.
[6] "La valeur consiste dans le rapport d'echange qui se
trouve entre telle chose et telle autre entre telle mesure d'une production et
telle mesure d'une autre." (Le Trosne: "De l'Interet Social." Physiocrates, Ed.
Daire. Paris, 1846. P. 889.)
[7] "Nothing can have an intrinsick value." (N. Barbon, t.
c., p. 6); or as Butler says -- "The value of a thing Is just as much as it will
bring."
[8] N. Barbon, l.c., p. 53 and 7.
[9] "The value of them (the necessaries of life), when they
are exchanged the one for another, is regulated by the quantity of labour
necessarily required, and commonly taken in producing them." ("Some Thoughts on
the Interest of Money in General, and Particularly in the Publick Funds, &."
Lond., p. 36) This remarkable anonymous work written in the last century, bears
no date. It is clear, however, from internal evidence that it appeared in the
reign of George II, about 1739 or 1740.
[10] "Toutes les productions d'un meme genre ne forment
proprement qu'une masse, dont le prix se determine en general et sans egard aux
circonstances particulieres." (Le Trosne, l.c., p. 893.)
[11] K. Marx. l.c., p.6.
[12] [Note in the 4th German edition: I am inserting the
parenthesis because its omission has often given rise to the misunderstanding
that every product that is consumed by some one other than its producer is
considered in Marx a commodity. -- F. E.]
[13] Tutti i fenomeni dell'universo, sieno essi prodotti
della mano dell'uomo, ovvero delle universali leggi della fisica, non ci danno
idea di attuale creazione, ma unicamente di una modificazione della materia.
Accostare e separare sono gli unici elementi che l'ingegno umano ritrova
analizzando l'idea della riproduzione: e tanto e riproduzione di valore (value
in use, although Verri in this passage of his controversy with the Physiocrats
is not himself quite certain of the kind of value he is speaking of) e di
ricchezze se la terra, I'aria e I'acqua ne' campi si trasmutino in grano, come
se colla mano dell'uomo il glutine di un insetto si trasmuti in velluto ovvero
alcuni pezzetti di metalio si organizzino a formare una ripetizione."-Pietro
Verri, "Meditazioni sulla Economia Politica" [first printed in 1773] in
Custodi's edition of the Italian Economists, Parte Moderna, t. XV., p. 22.
[14] Comp. Hegel, "Philosophie des Rechts." Berlin, 1840.
P. 250, 190.
[15] The reader must note that we are not speaking here of
the wages or value that the labourer gets for a given labour-time, but of the
value of the commodity in which that labour-time is materialised. Wages is a
category that, as yet, has no existence at the present stage of our
investigation.
[16] In order to prove that labour alone is that
all-sufficient and real measure, by which at all times the value of all
commodities can be estimated and compared, Adam Smith says, "Equal quantities of
labour must at all times and in all places have the same value for the labourer.
In his normal state of health, strength, and activity, and with the average
degree of skill that he may possess, he must always give up the same portion of
his rest his freedom, and his happiness." ("Wealth of Nations," b. I. ch. V.) On
the one hand Adam Smith here (but not everywhere) confuses the determination of
value by means of the quantity of labour expended in the production of
commodities, with the determination of the values of commodities by means of the
value of labour, and seeks in consequence to prove that equal quantities of
labour have always the same value. On the other hand he has a presentiment, that
labour, so far as it manifests itself in the value of commodities, counts only
as expenditure of labour-power, but he treats this expenditure as the mere
sacrifice of rest, freedom, and happiness, not as at the same time the normal
activity of living beings. But then, he has the modern wage-labourer in his eye.
Much more aptly, the anonymous predecessor of Adam Smith, quoted above in Note
1, p. 39 [note 9 etext]. says "one man has employed himself a week in providing
this necessary of life ... and he that gives him some other in exchange cannot
make a better estimate of what is a proper equivalent, than by computing what
cost him just as much labour and time which in effect is no more than exchanging
one man's labour in one thing for a time certain, for another man's labour in
another thing for the same time." (l.c., p. 39.) [The English language has the
advantage of possessing different words for the two aspects of labour here
considered. The labour which creates Use-Value, and counts qualitatively, is
Work, as distinguished from Labour, that which creates Value and counts
quantitatively, is Labour as distinguished from Work -F. E.]
[17] The few economists, amongst whom is S. Bailey, who
have occupied themselves with the analysis of the form of value, have been
unable to arrive at any result, first, because they confuse the form of value
with value itself; and second, because, under the coarse influence of the
practical bourgeois, they exclusively give their attention to the quantitative
aspect of the question. "The command of quantity ... constitutes value." ("Money
and its Vicissitudes." London, 1837, p. 11. By S. Bailey.)
[18] The celebrated Franklin, one of the first economists,
after Wm. Petty, who saw through the nature of value, says: "Trade in general
being nothing else but the exchange of labour for labour, the value of all
things is ... most justly measured by labour." ("The works of B. Franklin,
&c.," edited by Sparks. Boston, 1836, Vol. II., p. 267.) Franklin is
unconscious that by estimating the value of everything in labour, he makes
abstraction from any difference in the sorts of labour exchanged, and thus
reduces them all to equal human labour. But although ignorant of this, yet he
says it. He speaks first of "the one labour," then of "the other labour," and
finally of "labour," without further qualification, as the substance of the
value of everything.
[19] In a sort of way, it is with man as with commodities.
Since he comes into the world neither with a looking glass in his hand, nor as a
Fichtian philosopher, to whom "I am I" is sufficient, man first sees and
recognises himself in other men. Peter only establishes his own identity as a
man by first comparing himself with Paul as being of like kind. And thereby
Paul, just as he stands in his Pauline personality, becomes to Peter the type of
the genus homo.
[20] Value is here, as occasionally in the preceding
pages, used in sense of value determined as to quantity, or of magnitude of
value.
[21] This incongruity between the magnitude of value and
its relative expression has, with customary ingenuity, been exploited by vulgar
economists. For example -"Once admit that A falls, because B, with which it is
exchanged, rises, while no less labour is bestowed in the meantime on A, and
your general principle of value falls to the ground.... If he [Ricardo]
allowed that when A rises in value relatively to B, B falls in value relatively
to A, he cut away the ground on which he rested his grand proposition, that the
value of a commodity is ever determined by the labour embodied in it, for if a
change in the cost of A alters not only its own value in relation to B, for
which it is exchanged, but also the value of B relatively to that of A, though
no change has taken place in the quantity of labour to produce B, then not only
the doctrine falls to the ground which asserts that the quantity of labour
bestowed on an article regulates its value, but also that which affirms the cost
of an article to regulate its value' (J. Broadhurst: "Political Economy,"
London, 1842, pp. 11 and 14.) Mr. Broadhurst might just as well say: consider
the fractions 10/20, 10/50, 10/100, &c., the number 10 remains unchanged,
and yet its proportional magnitude, its magnitude relatively to the numbers 20,
50, 100 &c., continually diminishes. Therefore the great principle that the
magnitude of a whole number, such as 10, is "regulated" by the number of times
unity is contained in it, falls to the ground. [The author explains in section 4
of this chapter, pp. 80- 81, note 2 (note 33 etext), what he understands by
"Vulgar Economy." -- F. E.]
[22] Such expressions of relations in general, called by
Hegel reflex-categories, form a very curious class. For instance, one man is
king only because other men stand in the relation of subjects to him. They, on
the contrary, imagine that they are subjects because he is king.
[23] F. L. A. Ferrier, sous-inspecteur des douanes, "Du
gouvernement considere dans ses rapports avec le commerce," Paris, 1805; and
Charles Ganilh, "Des Systemes d'Economie Politique, -- 2nd ed., Paris, 1821.
[24] In Homer, for instance, the value of an article is
expressed in a series of different things II. Vll. 472-475.
[25] For this reason, we can speak of the coat-value of
the linen when its value is expressed in coats, or of its corn-value when
expressed in corn, and so on. Every such expression tells us, that what appears
in the use-values, cost, corn, &c., is the value of the linen. "The value of
any commodity denoting its relation in exchange, we may speak of it as ...
corn-value, cloth-value, according to the commodity with which it is compared;
and hence there are a thousand different kinds of value, as many kinds of value
as there are commodities in existence, and all are equally real and equally
nominal." ("A Critical Dissertation on the Nature, Measures and Causes of Value:
chiefly in reference to the writings of Mr. Ricardo and his followers." By the
author of "Essays on the Formation, &c., of Opinions. ' London, 1825, p.
39.) S. Bailey, the author of this anonymous work, a work which in its day
created much stir in England, fancied that, by thus pointing out the various
relative expressions of one and the same value, he had proved the impossibility
of any determination of the concept of value. However narrow his own views may
have been, yet, that he laid his finger on some serious defects in the Ricardian
Theory, is proved by the animosity with which he was attacked by Ricardo's
followers. See the Westminster Review for example.
[26] It is by no means self-evident that this character of
direct and universal exchangeability is, so to speak, a polar one, and as
intimately connected with its opposite pole, the absence of direct
exchangeability, as the positive pole of the magnet is with its negative
counterpart. It may therefore be imagined that all commodities can
simultaneously have this character impressed upon them, just as it can be
imagined that all Catholics can be popes together. It is, of course, highly
desirable in the eyes of the petit bourgeois, for whom the production of
commodities is the nec plus ultra of human freedom and individual independence,
that the inconveniences resulting from this character of commodities not being
directly exchangeable, should be removed. Proudhon's socialism is a working out
of this Philistine Utopia, a form of socialism which, as I have elsewhere shown,
does not possess even the merit of originality. Long before his time, the task
was attempted with much better success by Gray, Bray, and others. But, for all
that, wisdom of this kind flourishes even now in certain circles under the name
of "science." Never has any school played more tricks with the word science,
than that of Proudhon, for "wo Begriffe fehlen, Da stellt zur rechten Zeit ein
Wort sich ein."
[27] Among the ancient Germans the unit for rneasuring
land was what could be harvested in a day, and was called Tagwerk, Tagwanne
(jurnale, or terra jurnalis, or diornalis), Mannsmaad, &c. (See G. L. von
Maurer, "Einleitung zur Geschichte der Mark-, &c. Verfassung," Munchen,
1854, p. 129 sq.)
[28] When, therefore, Galiani says: Value is a relation
between persons -- "La Ricchezza e una ragione tra due persone," -- he ought to
have added: a relation between persons expressed as a relation between things.
(Galiani: Della Moneta, p. 221, V. III. of Custodi's collection of "Scrittori
Classici Italiani di Economia Politica." Parte Moderna, Milano 1803.)
[29] What are we to think of a law that asserts itself
only by periodical revolutions? It is just nothing but a law of Nature, founded
on the want of knowledge of those whose action is the subject of it." (Friedrich
Engels: "Umrisse zu einer Kritik der Nationalokonomie," in the
"Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbucher," edited by Arnold Ruge and Karl Marx. Paris.
1844.)
[30] Even Ricardo has his stories a la Robinson. "He makes
the primitive hunter and the primitive fisher straightway, as owners of
commodities, exchange fish and game in the proportion in which labour-time is
incorporated in these exchange-values. On this occasion he commits the
anachronism of making these men apply to the calculation, so far as their
implements have to be taken into account, the annuity tables in current use on
the London Exchange in the year 1817. The parallelograms of Mr. Owen' appear to
be the only form of society, besides the bourgeois form, with which he was
acquainted." (Karl Marx: "Zur Kritik, &c.." pp. 38, 39)
[31] 'A ridiculous presumption has latterly got abroad
that common property in its primitive form is specifically a Slavonian, or even
exclusively Russian form. It is the primitive form that we can prove to have
existed amongst Romans, Teutons, and Celts, and even to this day we find
numerous examples, ruins though they be, in India. A more exhaustive study of
Asiatic, and especially of Indian forms of common property, would show how from
the different forms of primitive common property, different forms of its
dissolution have been developed. Thus, for instance, the various original types
of Roman and Teutonic private property are deducible from different forms of
Indian common property." (Karl Marx, "Zur Kritik, &c.," p. 10.)
[32] The insufficiency of Ricardo's analysis of the
magnitude of value, and his analysis is by far the best, will appear from the
3rd and 4th books of this work. As regards value in general, it is the weak
point of the classical school of Political Economy that it nowhere expressly and
with full consciousness, distinguishes between labour, as it appears in the
value of a product, and the same labour, as it appears in the use-value of that
product. Of course the distinction is practically made, since this school treats
labour, at one time under its quantitative aspect, at another under its
qualitative aspect. But it has not the least idea, that when the difference
between various kinds of labour is treated as purely quantitative, their
qualitative unity or equality, and therefore their reduction to abstract human
labour, is implied. For instance, Ricardo declares that he agrees with Destutt
de Tracy in this proposition: "As it is certain that our physical and moral
faculties are alone our original riches, the employment of those faculties,
labour of some kind, is our only original treasure, and it is always from this
employment that all those things are created which we call riches.... It is
certain, too, that all those things only represent the labour which has created
them, and if they have a value, or even two distinct values, they can only
derive them from that (the value) of the labour from which they emanate."
(Ricardo, "The Principles of Pol. Econ.," 3 Ed. Lond. 1821, p. 334.) We would
here only point out, that Ricardo puts his own more profound interpretation upon
the words of Destutt. What the latter really says is, that on the one hand all
things which constitute wealth represent the labour that creates them, but that
on the other hand, they acquire their "two different values" (use-value and
exchange-value) from "the value of labour." He thus falls into the commonplace
error of the vulgar economists, who assume the value of one commodity (in this
case labour) in order to determine the values of the rest. But Ricardo reads him
as if he had said, that labour (not the value of labour) is embodied both in
use-value and exchange-value. Nevertheless, Ricardo himself pays so little
attention to the two-fold character of the labour which has a two-fold
embodiment, that he devotes the whole of his chapter on "Value and Riches, Their
Distinctive Properties," to a laborious examination of the trivialities of a
J.B. Say. And at the finish he is quite astonished to find that Destutt on the
one hand agrees with him as to labour being the source of value, and on the
other hand with J. B. Say as to the notion of value.
[33] It is one of the chief failings of classical economy
that it has never succeeded, by means of its analysis of commodities, and, in
particular, of their value, in discovering that form under which value becomes
exchange-value. Even Adam Smith and Ricardo, the best representatives of the
school, treat the form of value as a thing of no importance, as having no
connexion with the inherent nature of commodities. The reason for this is not
solely because their attention is entirely absorbed in the analysis of the
magnitude of value. It lies deeper. The value-form of the product of labour is
not only the most abstract, but is also the most universal form, taken by the
product in bourgeois production and stamps that production as a particular
species of social production, and thereby gives it its special historical
character. If then we treat this mode of production as one eternally fixed by
Nature for every state of society, we necessarily overlook that which is the
differentia specifica of the value-form, and consequently of the commodity-form,
and of its further developments, money-form, capital-form, &c. We
consequently find that economists, who are thoroughly agreed as to labour-time
being the measure of the magnitude of value, have the most strange and
contradictory ideas of money, the perfected form of the general equivalent. This
is seen in a striking manner when they treat of banking, where the commonplace
definitions of money will no longer hold water. This led to the rise of a
restored mercantile system (Ganilh, &c.), which sees in value nothing but a
social form, or rather the unsubstantial ghost of that form. Once for all I may
here state, that by classical Political Economy, I understand that economy
which, since the time of W. Petty, has investigated the real relations of
production in bourgeois society in contradistinction to vulgar economy, which
deals with appearances only, ruminates without ceasing on the materials long
since provided by scientific economy, and there seeks plausible explanations of
the most obtrusive phenomena, for bourgeois daily use, but for the rest,
confines itself to systematising in a pedantic way, and proclaiming for
everlasting truths, the trite ideas held by the self-complacent bourgeoisie with
regard to their own world, to them the best of all possible worlds.
[34] "Les economistes ont une singuliere maniere de
proceder. Il n'y a pour eux que deux sortes d'institutions, celles de l'art et
celles de la nature. Les institutions de la feodalite sont des institutions
artificielles celles de la bourgeoisie sont des institutions naturelles. Ils
ressemblent en ceci aux theologiens, qui eux aussi etablissent deux sortes de
religions. Toute religion qui n'est pas la leur, est une invention des hommes
tandis que leur propre religion est une emanation de Dieu -Ainsi il y a eu de
l'histoire, mais il n'y en a plus." (Karl Marx. Misere de la Philosophie.
Reponse a la Philosophie de la Misere par M. Proudhon, 1847, p. 113.) Truly
comical is M. Bastiat, who imagines that the ancient Greeks and Romans lived by
plunder alone. But when people plunder for centuries, there must always be
something at hand for them to seize; the objects of plunder must be continually
reproduced. It would thus appear that even Greeks and Romans had some process of
production, consequently, an economy, which just as much constituted the
material basis of their world, as bourgeois economy constitutes that of our
modern world. Or perhaps Bastiat means, that a mode of production based on
slavery is based on a system of plunder. In that case he treads on dangerous
ground. If a giant thinker like Aristotle erred in his appreciation of slave
labour, why should a dwarf economist like Bastiat be right in his appreciation
of wage-labour? I seize this opportunity of shortly answering an objection taken
by a German paper in America, to my work, "Zur Kritik der Pol. Oekonomie, 1859."
In the estimation of that paper, my view that each special mode of production
and the social relations corresponding to it, in short, that the economic
structure of society, is the real basis on which the juridical and political
superstructure is raised and to which definite social forms of thought
correspond; that the mode of production determines the character of the social,
political, and intellectual life generally, all this is very true for our own
times, in which material interests preponderate, but not for the middle ages, in
which Catholicism, nor for Athens and Rome, where politics, reigned supreme. In
the first place it strikes one as an odd thing for any one to suppose that these
well-worn phrases about the middle ages and the ancient world are unknown to
anyone else. This much, however, is clear, that the middle ages could not live
on Catholicism, nor the ancient world on politics. On the contrary, it is the
mode in which they gained a livelihood that explains why here politics, and
there Catholicism, played the chief part. For the rest, it requires but a slight
acquaintance with the history of the Roman republic, for example, to be aware
that its secret history is the history of its landed property. On the other
hand, Don Quixote long ago paid the penalty for wrongly imagining that knight
errantry was compatible with all economic forms of society.
[35] "Observations on certain verbal disputes in Pol.
Econ., particularly relating to value and to demand and supply" Lond., 1821, p.
16.
[36] S. Bailey, l.c., p. 165.
[37] The author of "Observations" and S. Bailey accuse
Ricardo of converting exchange-value from something relative into something
absolute. The opposite is the fact. He has explained the apparent relation
between objects, such as diamonds and pearls, in which relation they appear as
exchange-values, and disclosed the true relation hidden behind the appearances,
namely, their relation to each other as mere expressions of human labour. If the
followers of Ricardo answer Bailey somewhat rudely, and by no means
convincingly, the reason is to be sought in this, that they were unable to find
in Ricardo's own works any key to the hidden relations existing between value
and its form, exchange-value.
Transcribed for the Internet by Bert Schultz
THE TWO-FOLD CHARACTER OF
THE LABOUR EMBODIED
IN COMMODITIES
THE FORM OF VALUE OR EXCHANGE-VALUE
x commodity A = y commodity B, or
x commodity A is worth y
commodity B.
20 Yards of linen are worth 1 coat.
5 beds = 1 house
is not to be distinguished from
(clinai pente anti oiciaV)
5 beds = so much money.
He further sees that the value-relation which gives rise to this
expression makes it necessary that the house should qualitatively be made the
equal of the bed, and that, without such an equalisation, these two clearly
different things could not be compared with each other as commensurable
quantities. "Exchange," he says, "cannot take place without equality, and
equality not without commensurability". (out isothV mh oushV snmmetriaV). Here,
however, he comes to a stop, and gives up the further analysis of the form of
value. "It is, however, in reality, impossible (th men oun alhqeia adunaton),
that such unlike things can be commensurable" -- i.e., qualitatively
equal. Such an equalisation can only be something foreign to their real nature,
consequently only "a makeshift for practical purposes."
(clinai pente anti . . . dson ai pente
clinai)
z Com. A = u Com. B or
= v Com. C or
= w Com. D or
= x Com. E or
= &c.
(20 yards of linen = 1 coat or
= 10 lbs. tea or
= 40 lbs. coffee or
= quarter corn or
= 2 ounces gold or
= 1/2 ton iron or
= &c.)
20 yards of linen = 1 coat
Each of these implies the corresponding inverted equation,
20 yards of linen = 10 Ibs. of tea, etc.
1 coat = 20 yards of linen
In fact, when a person exchanges his linen for many other
commodities, and thus expresses its value in a series of other commodities, it
necessarily follows, that the various owners of the latter exchange them for the
linen, and consequently express the value of their various commodities in one
and the same third commodity, the linen. If then, we reverse the series, 20
yards of linen = 1 coat or = 10 Ibs. of tea, etc., that is to say, if we give
expression to the converse relation already implied in the series, we get,
10 Ibs. of tea = 20 yards of linen, etc.
1 coat \
10 Ibs. of tea |
40 lbs. of coffee |
1 quarter of corn |-- > = 20 yards of linen
2 ounces of gold |
1/2 a ton of iron |
x com A., etc. /
20 yards of linen \
1 coat |
10 lbs. of tea |
40 lbs. of coffee | -- > = 2 ounces of gold
1 qr. of corn |
1/2 a ton of iron |
x commodity A /
In passing from form A to form B, and from the latter to form C,
the changes are fundamental. On the other hand, there is no difference between
forms C and D, except that, in the latter, gold has assumed the equivalent form
in the place of linen. Gold is in form D, what linen was in form C -- the
universal equivalent. The progress consists in this alone, that the character of
direct and universal exchangeability -- in other words, that the universal
equivalent form -- has now, by social custom, become finally identified with the
substance, gold.
20 yards of linen = 2 ounces of gold, or,
The difficulty in forming a concept of the money-form, consists in
clearly comprehending the universal equivalent form, and as a necessary
corollary, the general form of value, form C. The latter is deducible from form
B, the expanded form of value, the essential component element of which, we saw,
is form A, 20 yards of linen = 1 coat or x commodity A = y commodity B. The
simple commodity-form is therefore the germ of the money-form.
if 2 ounces of gold
when coined are £2, 20 yards of linen = £2.
THE FETISHISM OF COMMODITIES
AND THE SECRET
THEREOF
On to
chapter 2
Capital, vol.
1
Table of contents
Marx/Engels
Internet Library
Marx/Engels
Internet Archive